LightNovesOnl.com

Complexity - A Guided Tour Part 9

Complexity - A Guided Tour - LightNovelsOnl.com

You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.

G: 25435515325623525105635546115133615415103415611055015005203025 62561322523503251120523330540552312550513361541506652641502665 06012264453605631520256431054354632404350334153250253251352352 045150130156213436252353223135051260513356201524514343432.

Staring at the genome of a strategy doesn't help us too much in understanding how that strategy works. We can see a few genes that make sense, such as the important situations in which Robby's current site contains a can, such as the second situation ("Empty Empty Empty Empty Can"), which has action 5 (PickUp) in both strategies. Such situations always have action 5 in M, but only most of the time in G. For example, I managed to determine that the following situation has action 3 (MoveWest), which means Robby doesn't pick up the can in his current site. This seems like a bad idea, yet G does better than M overall! The key, it turns out, is not these isolated genes, but the way different genes interact, just as has been found in real genetics. And just as in real genetics, it's very difficult to figure out how these various interactions lead to the overall behavior or fitness.

It makes more sense to look at the actual behavior of each strategy-its phenotype-rather than its genome. I wrote a graphics program to display Robby's moves when using a given strategy, and spent some time watching the behavior of Robby when he used strategy M and when he used strategy G. Although the two strategies behave similarly in many situations, I found that strategy G employs two tricks that cause it to perform better than strategy M.

First, consider a situation in which Robby does not sense a can in his current site or in any of his neighboring sites. If Robby is following strategy M, he chooses a random move to make. However, if he is following strategy G, Robby moves to the east until he either finds a can or reaches a wall. He then moves north, and continues to circle the edge of the grid in a counterclockwise direction until a can is encountered or sensed. This is ill.u.s.trated in figure 9.3 by the path Robby takes under each strategy (dotted line).

FIGURE 9.3. Robby in a "no-can" wilderness. The dotted lines show the paths he took in my simulation when he was following strategies M (top) and G (bottom).



FIGURE 9.4. Robby in a cl.u.s.ter of cans, using strategy M over four time steps.

Not only does this circle-the-perimeter strategy prevent Robby from cras.h.i.+ng into walls (a possibility under M whenever a random move is made), but it also turns out that circling the perimeter is a more efficient way to encounter cans than simply moving at random.

Second, with G the genetic algorithm discovered a neat trick by having Robby not pick up a can in his current site in certain situations.

For example, consider the situation ill.u.s.trated in figure 9.4a. Given this situation, if Robby is following M, he will pick up the can in his current site, move west, and then pick up the can in his new site (pictures bd). Because Robby can see only immediately adjacent sites, he now cannot see the remaining cl.u.s.ter of cans. He will have to move around at random until he encounters another can by chance.

In contrast, consider the same starting situation with G, ill.u.s.trated in figure 9.5a. Robby doesn't pick up the can in his current site; instead he moves west (figure 9.5b). He then picks up the western-most can of the cl.u.s.ter (figure 9.5c). The can he didn't pick up on the last move acts as a marker so Robby can "remember" that there are cans on the other side of it. He goes on to pick up all of the remaining cans in the cl.u.s.ter (figure 9.5d9.5k).

FIGURE 9.5. Robby in the same cl.u.s.ter of cans, using strategy G over eleven time steps. (Continued on next page) I knew that my strategy wasn't perfect, but this little trick never occurred to me. Evolution can be pretty clever. GAs often come up with things we humans don't consider.

Geneticists often test their theories about gene function by doing "knockout mutations," in which they use genetic engineering techniques to prevent the genes in question from being transcribed and see what effect that has on the organism. I can do the same thing here. In particular, I did an experiment in which I "knocked out" the genes in G that made this trick possible: I changed genes such that each gene that corresponds to a "can in current site" situation has the action PickUp. This lowered the average score of G from its original 483 to 443, which supports my hypothesis that this trick is partly responsible for G's success.

How Did the GA Evolve a Good Strategy?

The next question is, how did the GA, starting with a random population, manage to evolve such a good strategy as G?

To answer this question, let's look at how strategies improved over generations. In figure 9.6, I plot the fitness of the best strategy in each generation in my run of the GA. You can see that the best fitness starts out way below zero, rises very quickly until about generation 300, and then improves more slowly for the rest of the run.

FIGURE 9.6. Plot of best fitness in the population versus generation for the run of the GA in which strategy G was evolved.

The first generation consists of 200 randomly generated strategies. As you might expect, all of them are very, very bad. The best one has fitness of only 81 and the worst one has fitness 825.

I looked at the behavior of Robby when using the worst strategy of this generation, on several sessions, each starting with a different environment (configuration of cans). In some environments, Robby makes a few moves, then gets stuck, executing action StayPut again and again, for the entire session. In others he spends the session cras.h.i.+ng into a wall over and over again. In others he spends his whole time trying to pick up a nonexistent can in his current site. No surprise that evolution weeded out this strategy quite early on.

I also looked at the behavior of Robby using the best strategy of this generation, which is still a pretty bad one that gets stuck in ways similar to those in the worst strategy. However, it has a couple of advantages over the worst one: it is less likely to continually crash into a wall, and it occasionally moves into a site with a can and actually picks up the can! This being the best strategy of its generation, it has an excellent chance of being selected to reproduce. When it indeed is selected, its children inherit these good traits (along with lots of bad traits).

By the tenth generation, the fitness of the best strategy in the population has risen all the way to zero. This strategy usually gets stuck in a StayPut loop, occasionally getting stuck in a cycle moving back and forth between two sites. Very occasionally it crashes into walls. And like its ancestor from the first generation, it very occasionally picks up cans.

The GA continues its gradual improvement in best fitness. By generation 200 the best strategy has discovered the all-important trait of moving to sites with cans and then picking up those cans-at least a lot of the time. However, when stranded in a no-can wilderness, it wastes a lot of time by making random moves, similar to strategy M. By generation 250 a strategy equal in quality to M has been found, and by generation 400, the fitness is up beyond the 400 level, with a strategy that would be as good as G if only it made fewer random moves. By generation 800 the GA has discovered the trick of leaving cans as markers for adjacent cans, and by generation 900 the trick of finding and then moving around the perimeter of the world has been nearly perfected, requiring only a few tweaks to get it right by generation 1,000.

Although Robby the robot is a relatively simple example for teaching people about GAs, it is not all that different from the way GAs are used in the real world. And as in the example of Robby, in real-world applications, the GA will often evolve a solution that works, but it's hard to see why it works. That is often because GAs find good solutions that are quite different from the ones humans would come up with. Jason Lohn, a genetic algorithms expert from the National Astronautical and s.p.a.ce Administration (NASA), emphasizes this point: "Evolutionary algorithms are a great tool for exploring the dark corners of design s.p.a.ce. You show [your designs] to people with 25 years' experience in the industry and they say 'Wow, does that really work?'.... We frequently see evolved designs that are completely unintelligible."

In Lohn's case, unintelligible as it might be, it does indeed work. In 2005 Lohn and his colleagues won a "Human Compet.i.tive" award for their GA's design of a novel antenna for NASA s.p.a.cecraft, reflecting the fact that the GA's design was an improvement over that of human engineers.

PART III.

Computation Writ Large.

The proper domain of computer science is information processing writ large across all of nature.

-Chris Langton (Quoted in Roger Lewin, Complexity: Life at the Edge of Chaos).

CHAPTER 10.

Cellular Automata, Life, and the Universe.

Computation in Nature.

A recent article in Science magazine, called "Getting the Behavior of Social Insects to Compute," described the work of a group of entomologists who characterize the behavior of ant colonies as "computer algorithms," with each individual ant running a simple program that allows the colony as a whole to perform a complex computation, such as reaching a consensus on when and where to move the colony's nest.

This would be an easy computation for me to program on my computer: I could just appoint one (virtual) ant as leader and decision maker. All the other ants would simply observe the leader's decision and follow it. However, as we have seen, in ant colonies there is no leader; the ant-colony "computer" consists of millions of autonomous ants, each of which can base its decisions and actions only on the small fraction of other ants it happens to interact with. This leads to a kind of computation very different from the kind our desktop computers perform with a central processing unit and random-access memory.

Along the same lines, a 1994 article by three prominent brain researchers asked, "Is the brain a computer?" and answered, "If we embrace a broader concept of computation, then the answer is a definite Yes." Like ant colonies, it is clear that the way the brain computes-with billions of neurons working in parallel without central control-is very different from the way current-day digital computers work.

In the previous two chapters we explored the notion of life and evolution occurring in computers. In this part of the book, we look at the opposite notion; the extent to which computation itself occurs in nature. In what sense do natural systems "compute"? At a very general level, one might say that computation is what a complex system does with information in order to succeed or adapt in its environment. But can we make this statement more precise? Where is the information, and what exactly does the complex system do with it?

In order to make questions like this more amenable to study, scientists generally will idealize the problem-that is, simplify it as much as possible while still retaining the features that make the problem interesting.

In this spirit of simplification, many people have studied computation in nature via an idealized model of a complex system called a cellular automaton.

Cellular Automata.

Recall from chapter 4 that Turing machines provide a way of formalizing the notion of "definite procedure"-that is, computation. A computation is the transformation of the input initially on a Turing machine's tape, via the machine's set of rules, to the output on its tape after the halt state is reached. This abstract machine inspired the design of all subsequent digital computers. Because of John von Neumann's contribution to this design, our current-day computers are called "von-Neumann-style architectures."

The von-Neumann-style architecture consists of a random access memory (RAM) that stores both program instructions and data, and a central processing unit (CPU) that fetches instructions and data from memory and executes the instructions on the data. As you probably know, although programmers write instructions in high-level programming languages, instructions and data are actually stored in the computer as strings of 1s and 0s. Instructions are executed by translating such bit strings into simple logic operations applied to the data, which are then computed by the CPU. Only a few types of simple logic operators are needed to perform any computation, and today's CPUs can compute billions of these logic operations per second.

A cellular automaton, being an idealized version of a complex system, has a very different kind of architecture. Imagine a grid of battery-powered lightbulbs, as shown in figure 10.1. Each lightbulb is connected to all of its neighboring lightbulbs in the north, south, east, west, and diagonal directions. In the figure, these connections are shown for only one of the lightbulbs, but imagine that all the other ones have corresponding connections.

FIGURE 10.1. An array of lightbulbs, each of which is connected to its neighbors in the north, south, east, west, and diagonal directions, as is ill.u.s.trated for one of the lightbulbs. Each lightbulb can either be in state on or state off. Imagine that all four edges wrap around in a circular fas.h.i.+on-for example, the upper left bulb has the upper right bulb as its western neighbor and the lower left bulb as its northern neighbor.

In figure 10.2 (left box), some of the lightbulbs have been turned on (to make the figure simpler, I didn't draw the connections). After this initial configuration of on and off lightbulbs has been set up, each lightbulb will run a clock that tells it when to "update its state"-that is, turn on or off; and all the clocks are synchronized so all lightbulbs update their states at the same time, over and over again. You can think of the grid as a model of fireflies flas.h.i.+ng or turning off in response to the flashes of nearby fireflies, or of neurons firing or being inhibited by the actions of close-by neurons, or, if you prefer, simply as a work of abstract art.

How does a lightbulb "decide" whether to turn on or off at each time step? Each bulb follows a rule that is a function of the states in its neighborhood-that is, its own state (i.e., on or off) and those of the eight neighbors to which it is connected.

For example, let's say that the rule followed by each lightbulb is, "If the majority of bulbs in my neighborhood (including myself) are on, turn on (or stay on, if already on), otherwise turn off (or stay off, if already off)." That is, for each neighborhood of nine bulbs, if five or more of them are on, then the middle one is on at the next time step. Let's look at what the lightbulb grid does after one time step.

FIGURE 10.2. Left: The same array of lightbulbs as in figure 10.1, set up in an initial configuration of on and off states. Connections between lightbulbs are not shown. Right: each bulb's state has been updated according to the rule "take on whichever state is a majority in my local neighborhood."

As explained in the caption to figure 10.1, to make sure that each lightbulb indeed has eight neighbors, we will give the grid circular boundaries. Imagine that the top edge is folded over and touches the bottom edge, and the left edge is folded over and touches the right edge, forming a donut shape. This gives every lightbulb eight neighbors.

Now let's go back to the rule defined above. Figure 10.2 shows the initial grid and its configuration after following the rule for one time step.

I could have defined a more complicated rule, such as, "If at least two but no more than seven bulbs in my neighborhood are on, then turn on, otherwise turn off," and the updated grid would have looked different. Or "if exactly one bulb is off or exactly four bulbs are on in my neighborhood, turn off, otherwise turn on." There are lots of possibilities.

Exactly how many possible different rules could be defined? "Lots" is really understating it. The answer is "two raised to the power 512" (2512), a huge number, many times larger than the number of atoms in the universe. (See the notes to find out how this answer was derived.) This grid of lightbulbs is a cellular automaton. More generally, a cellular automaton is a grid (or lattice)of cells, where a cell is a simple unit that turns on or off in response to the states in its local neighborhood. (In general, cells can be defined with any number of states, but here we'll just talk about the on/off kind.) A cellular automaton rule-also called a cell update rule-is simply the identical rule followed by each cell, which tells the cell what its state should be at the next time step as a function of the current states in its local neighborhood.

Why do I say that such a simple system is an idealized model of a complex system? Like complex systems in nature, cellular automata are composed of large numbers of simple components (i.e., cells), with no central controller, each of which communicates with only a small fraction of the other components. Moreover, cellular automata can exhibit very complex behavior that is difficult or impossible to predict from the cell update rule.

Cellular automata were invented-like so many other good ideas-by John von Neumann, back in the 1940s, based on a suggestion by his colleague, the mathematician Stan Ulam. (This is a great irony of computer science, since cellular automata are often referred to as non -von-Neumann-style architectures, to contrast with the von-Neumann-style architectures that von Neumann also invented.) As I described in chapter 8, von Neumann was trying to formalize the logic of self-reproduction in machines, and he chose cellular automata as a way to approach this problem. In short, he was able to design a cellular automaton rule, in his case with twenty-nine states per cell instead of just two, that would create a perfect reproduction of any initial pattern placed on the cellular automaton lattice.

Von Neumann also was able to show that his cellular automaton was equivalent to a universal Turing machine (cf. chapter 4). The cell update rule plays the role of the rules for the Turing machine tape head, and the configuration of states plays the role of the Turing machine tape-that is, it encodes the program and data for the universal machine to run. The step-by-step updates of the cells correspond to the step-by-step iteration of the universal Turing machine. Systems that are equivalent in power to universal Turing machines (i.e., can compute anything that a universal Turing machine can) are more generally called universal computers, or are said to be capable of universal computation or to support universal computation.

The Game of Life.

Von Neumann's cellular automaton rule was rather complicated; a much simpler, two-state cellular automaton also capable of universal computation was invented in 1970 by the mathematician John Conway. He called his invention the "Game of Life." I'm not sure where the "game" part comes in, but the "life" part comes from the way in which Conway phrased the rule. Denoting on cells as alive and off cells as dead, Conway defined the rule in terms of four life processes: birth, a dead cell with exactly three live neighbors becomes alive at the next time step; survival, a live cell with exactly two or three live neighbors stays alive; loneliness, a live cell with fewer than two neighbors dies and a dead cell with fewer than three neighbors stays dead; and overcrowding, a live or dead cell with more than three live neighbors dies or stays dead.

FIGURE 10.3. Close-up picture of a glider in the Game of Life. After four time steps, the original glider configuration has moved in the southeast direction.

Conway came up with this cellular automaton rule when looking for a rule that would create interesting (or perhaps life-like) behavior. Indeed the Game of Life has plenty of interesting behavior and there is a whole community of Life aficionados whose main hobby is to discover initial patterns that will create such behavior.

One simple pattern with interesting behavior is the glider, ill.u.s.trated in figure 10.3. Here, instead of lightbulbs, I simply represent on (live) states by black squares and off (dead) states by white squares. The figure shows a glider "moving" in a southeast direction from its initial position. Of course, it's not the cells that move; they are all fixed in place. The moving ent.i.ties are on states that form a coherent, persisting shape. Since, as I mentioned earlier, the cellular automaton's boundaries wrap around to create a donut shape, the glider will continue moving around and around the lattice forever.

Other intricate patterns that have been discovered by enthusiasts include the s.p.a.ces.h.i.+p, a fancier type of glider, and the glider gun, which continually shoots out new gliders. Conway showed how to simulate Turing machines in Life by having the changing on/ off patterns of states simulate a tape head that reads and writes on a simulated tape.

John Conway also sketched a proof (later refined by others) that Life could simulate a universal computer. This means that given an initial configuration of on and off states that encodes a program and the input data for that program, Life will run that program on that data, producing a pattern that represents the program's output.

Conway's proof consisted of showing how glider guns, gliders, and other structures could be a.s.sembled so as to carry out the logical operations and, or, and not. It has long been known that any machine that has the capacity to put together all possible combinations of these logic operations is capable of universal computation. Conway's proof demonstrated that, in principle, all such combinations of logical operations are possible in the Game of Life.

It's fascinating to see that something as simple to define as the Life cellular automaton can, in principle, run any program that can be run on a standard computer. However, in practice, any nontrivial computation will require a large collection of logic operations, interacting in specific ways, and it is very difficult, if not impossible, to design initial configurations that will achieve nontrivial computations. And even if it were possible, the ensuing computation would be achingly slow, not to mention wasteful, since the huge parallel, non-von-Neumann-style computing resources of the cellular automaton would be used to simulate, in a very slow manner, a traditional von-Neumann-style computer.

For these reasons, people don't use Life (or other "universal" cellular automata) to perform real-world computations or even to model natural systems. What we really want from cellular automata is to harness their parallelism and ability to form complex patterns in order to achieve computations in a nontraditional way. The first step is to characterize the kinds of patterns that cellular automata can form.

The Four Cla.s.ses.

In the early 1980s, Stephen Wolfram, a physicist working at the Inst.i.tute for Advanced Study in Princeton, became fascinated with cellular automata and the patterns they make. Wolfram is one of those legendary former child prodigies whom people like to tell stories about. Born in London in 1959, Wolfram published his first physics paper at age 15. Two years later, in the summer after his first year at Oxford, a time when typical college students get jobs as lifeguards or hitchhike around Europe with a backpack, Wolfram wrote a paper in the field of "quantum chromodynamics" that caught the attention of n.o.bel prizewinning physicist Murray Gell-Mann, who invited Wolfram to join his group at Caltech (California Inst.i.tute of Technology). Two years later, at age twenty, Wolfram received a Ph.D. in theoretical physics. (Most students take at least five years to get a Ph.D., after graduating from college.) He then joined the Caltech faculty, and was soon awarded one of the first MacArthur Foundation "genius" grants. A couple of years later, he was invited to join the faculty at the Inst.i.tute for Advanced Study in Princeton.

Stephen Wolfram. (Photograph courtesy of Wolfram Research, Inc.) Whew. With all that fame, funding, and the freedom to do whatever he wanted, Wolfram chose to study the dynamics of cellular automata.

In the spirit of good theoretical physics, Wolfram set out to study the behavior of cellular automata in the simplest form possible-using one-dimensional, two-state cellular automata in which each cell is connected only to its two nearest neighbors (figure 10.4a). Wolfram termed these "elementary cellular automata." He figured that if he couldn't understand what was going on in these seemingly ultra-simple systems, there was no chance of understanding more complex (e.g., two-dimensional or multistate) cellular automata.

Figure 10.4 ill.u.s.trates one particular elementary cellular automaton rule. Figure 10.4a shows the lattice-now just a line of cells, each connected to its nearest neighbor on either side. As before, a cell is represented by a square-black for on, and white for off. The edges of the lattice wrap around to make a circle. Figure 10.4b shows the rule that each cell follows: for each of the eight possible state configurations for a three-cell neighborhood, the update state for the center cell is given. For example, whenever a three-cell neighborhood consists of all off states, the center cell should stay off at the next time step. Likewise, whenever a three-cell neighborhood has the configuration off-off-on, the center cell should change its state to on at the next time step. Note that the term rule refers to the entire list of configurations and update states, not to the individual lines in the list. Figure 10.4c shows a s.p.a.ce-time diagram for this cellular automaton. The top row of cells is the one-dimensional lattice set up with a particular initial configuration of on and off states. Each successive row going down is the updated lattice at the next time step. Such plots are called s.p.a.ce-time diagrams because they track the spatial configuration of a cellular automaton over a number of time steps.

FIGURE 10.4. (a) An ill.u.s.tration of a one-dimensional lattice whose ends wrap around in a circle; (b) A particular elementary cellular automaton rule (Rule 110) expressed as a list of three-cell configurations and corresponding update states for the configuration's center cell; (c) A s.p.a.ce-time diagram, showing four successive configurations of the cellular automaton.

Since there are only eight possible configurations of states for a three-cell neighborhood (cf. figure 10.4b) and only two possible ways to fill in the update state (on or off) for each of these eight configurations, there are only 256 (28) possible rules for elementary cellular automata. By the 1980s, computers were powerful enough for Wolfram to thoroughly investigate every single one of them by looking at their behavior starting from many different initial lattice configurations.

Wolfram a.s.signed an identifying number to each elementary cellular automaton rule as ill.u.s.trated in figure 10.5. He called the on state "1" and the off state "0," and wrote the rule's update states as a string of 1s and 0s, starting with the update state for the all on neighborhood and ending with the update state for the all off neighborhood. As shown, the rule given in figure 10.4 is written as 01101110. Wolfram then interpreted this string as a number written in binary (i.e., base 2). The string 01101110 in binary is equal to the number 110 in decimal. This rule is thus called "Rule 110." As another example, the rule with update states 00011110 is "Rule 30." (See the notes for a review on how to convert base 2 numbers to decimal.) FIGURE 10.5. An ill.u.s.tration of the numbering system for elementary cellular automata used by Stephen Wolfram.

FIGURE 10.6. Rule 110 s.p.a.ce-time diagram. The one-dimensional cellular automaton lattice has 200 cells, which are shown starting with a random initial configuration of states, and updating over 200 time steps.

Wolfram and his colleagues developed a special programming language, called Mathematica, designed in part to make it easy to simulate cellular automata. Using Mathematica, Wolfram programmed his computer to run elementary cellular automata and to display s.p.a.ce-time diagrams that show their behavior. For example, figures 10.6 and 10.7 are plots like that given in figure 10.4, just on a larger scale. The top horizontal row of figure 10.6 is a random initial configuration of 200 black and white cells, and each successive row is the result of applying Rule 110 to each cell in the previous row, for 200 time steps. The plot in figure 10.7 shows the pattern created by Rule 30, starting from a random initial configuration.

FIGURE 10.7. Rule 30 s.p.a.ce-time diagram, with an initial configuration of random states.

Looking at figures 10.6 and 10.7, perhaps you can sense why Wolfram got so excited about elementary cellular automata. How, exactly, did these complex patterns emerge from the very simple cellular automaton rules that created them?

Seeing such complexity emerge from simple rules was evidently an epiphany for Wolfram. He later said, "The Rule 30 automaton is the most surprising thing I've ever seen in science.... It took me several years to absorb how important this was. But in the end, I realized that this one picture contains the clue to what's perhaps the most long-standing mystery in all of science: where, in the end, the complexity of the natural world comes from." In fact, Wolfram was so impressed by Rule 30 that he patented its use as part of a pseudo-random number generator.

In Wolfram's exhaustive survey of all 256 elementary cellular automata, he viewed the behavior over time of each one starting from many different initial configurations. For each elementary cellular automaton and each initial configuration, he applied the cellular automaton rule to the lattice for a number of time steps-until the cellular automaton exhibited a stable type of behavior. He observed the behavior to fall into four cla.s.ses: Cla.s.s 1: Almost all initial configurations settle down to the same uniform final pattern. Rule 8 is an example of this cla.s.s; for all initial configurations, all cells in the lattice quickly switch to the off state and stay that way.

Cla.s.s 2: Almost all initial configurations settle down to either a uniform final pattern or a cycling between a few final patterns. Here, the specific final pattern or patterns depends on the initial configuration.

Cla.s.s 3: Most initial configurations produce random-looking behavior, although triangles or other regular structures are present. Rule 30 (figure 10.7) is an example of this cla.s.s.

Cla.s.s 4: The most interesting cla.s.s. As described by Wolfram: "cla.s.s 4 involves a mixture of order and randomness: localized structures are produced which on their own are fairly simple, but these structures move around and interact with each other in very complicated ways." Rule 110 (figure 10.6) is an example of this cla.s.s.

Wolfram speculated that, because of this complexity of patterns and interactions, all cla.s.s 4 rules are capable of universal computation. However, in general it is hard to prove that a particular cellular automaton, Turing machine, or any other device is universal. Turing's proof that there exists a universal Turing machine was a triumph, as was von Neumann's proof that his self-replicating automaton was also a universal computer. Since then several researchers have proved that simple cellular automata (such as the Game of Life) are universal. In the 1990s, Matthew Cook, one of Wolfram's research a.s.sistants, finally proved that Rule 110 was indeed universal, and is perhaps the simplest known example of a universal computer.

Click Like and comment to support us!

RECENTLY UPDATED NOVELS

About Complexity - A Guided Tour Part 9 novel

You're reading Complexity - A Guided Tour by Author(s): Melanie Mitchell. This novel has been translated and updated at LightNovelsOnl.com and has already 535 views. And it would be great if you choose to read and follow your favorite novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest novels, a novel list updates everyday and free. LightNovelsOnl.com is a very smart website for reading novels online, friendly on mobile. If you have any questions, please do not hesitate to contact us at [email protected] or just simply leave your comment so we'll know how to make you happy.