LightNovesOnl.com

Theory of the Leisure Class Part 1

Theory of the Leisure Class - LightNovelsOnl.com

You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.

The Theory of the Leisure Cla.s.s.

by Thorstein Veblen.

Chapter One -- Introductory

The inst.i.tution of a leisure cla.s.s is found in its best development at the higher stages of the barbarian culture; as, for instance, in feudal Europe or feudal j.a.pan. In such communities the distinction between cla.s.ses is very rigorously observed; and the feature of most striking economic significance in these cla.s.s differences is the distinction maintained between the employments proper to the several cla.s.ses.

The upper cla.s.ses are by custom exempt or excluded from industrial occupations, and are reserved for certain employments to which a degree of honour attaches. Chief among the honourable employments in any feudal community is warfare; and priestly service is commonly second to warfare. If the barbarian community is not notably warlike, the priestly office may take the precedence, with that of the warrior second. But the rule holds with but slight exceptions that, whether warriors or priests, the upper cla.s.ses are exempt from industrial employments, and this exemption is the economic expression of their superior rank. Brahmin India affords a fair ill.u.s.tration of the industrial exemption of both these cla.s.ses. In the communities belonging to the higher barbarian culture there is a considerable differentiation of sub-cla.s.ses within what may be comprehensively called the leisure cla.s.s; and there is a corresponding differentiation of employments between these sub-cla.s.ses.

The leisure cla.s.s as a whole comprises the n.o.ble and the priestly cla.s.ses, together with much of their retinue. The occupations of the cla.s.s are correspondingly diversified; but they have the common economic characteristic of being non-industrial. These non-industrial upper-cla.s.s occupations may be roughly comprised under government, warfare, religious observances, and sports.

At an earlier, but not the earliest, stage of barbarism, the leisure cla.s.s is found in a less differentiated form. Neither the cla.s.s distinctions nor the distinctions between leisure-cla.s.s occupations are so minute and intricate. The Polynesian islanders generally show this stage of the development in good form, with the exception that, owing to the absence of large game, hunting does not hold the usual place of honour in their scheme of life. The Icelandic community in the time of the Sagas also affords a fair instance. In such a community there is a rigorous distinction between cla.s.ses and between the occupations peculiar to each cla.s.s. Manual labour, industry, whatever has to do directly with the everyday work of getting a livelihood, is the exclusive occupation of the inferior cla.s.s. This inferior cla.s.s includes slaves and other dependents, and ordinarily also all the women. If there are several grades of aristocracy, the women of high rank are commonly exempt from industrial employment, or at least from the more vulgar kinds of manual labour. The men of the upper cla.s.ses are not only exempt, but by prescriptive custom they are debarred, from all industrial occupations. The range of employments open to them is rigidly defined. As on the higher plane already spoken of, these employments are government, warfare, religious observances, and sports. These four lines of activity govern the scheme of life of the upper cla.s.ses, and for the highest rank--the kings or chieftains--these are the only kinds of activity that custom or the common sense of the community will allow.

Indeed, where the scheme is well developed even sports are accounted doubtfully legitimate for the members of the highest rank. To the lower grades of the leisure cla.s.s certain other employments are open, but they are employments that are subsidiary to one or another of these typical leisure-cla.s.s occupations. Such are, for instance, the manufacture and care of arms and accoutrements and of war canoes, the dressing and handling of horses, dogs, and hawks, the preparation of sacred apparatus, etc. The lower cla.s.ses are excluded from these secondary honourable employments, except from such as are plainly of an industrial character and are only remotely related to the typical leisure-cla.s.s occupations.

If we go a step back of this exemplary barbarian culture, into the lower stages of barbarism, we no longer find the leisure cla.s.s in fully developed form. But this lower barbarism shows the usages, motives, and circ.u.mstances out of which the inst.i.tution of a leisure cla.s.s has arisen, and indicates the steps of its early growth. Nomadic hunting tribes in various parts of the world ill.u.s.trate these more primitive phases of the differentiation. Any one of the North American hunting tribes may be taken as a convenient ill.u.s.tration. These tribes can scarcely be said to have a defined leisure cla.s.s. There is a differentiation of function, and there is a distinction between cla.s.ses on the basis of this difference of function, but the exemption of the superior cla.s.s from work has not gone far enough to make the designation "leisure cla.s.s" altogether applicable. The tribes belonging on this economic level have carried the economic differentiation to the point at which a marked distinction is made between the occupations of men and women, and this distinction is of an invidious character. In nearly all these tribes the women are, by prescriptive custom, held to those employments out of which the industrial occupations proper develop at the next advance. The men are exempt from these vulgar employments and are reserved for war, hunting, sports, and devout observances. A very nice discrimination is ordinarily shown in this matter.

This division of labour coincides with the distinction between the working and the leisure cla.s.s as it appears in the higher barbarian culture. As the diversification and specialisation of employments proceed, the line of demarcation so drawn comes to divide the industrial from the non-industrial employments. The man's occupation as it stands at the earlier barbarian stage is not the original out of which any appreciable portion of later industry has developed. In the later development it survives only in employments that are not cla.s.sed as industrial,--war, politics, sports, learning, and the priestly office.

The only notable exceptions are a portion of the fishery industry and certain slight employments that are doubtfully to be cla.s.sed as industry; such as the manufacture of arms, toys, and sporting goods.

Virtually the whole range of industrial employments is an outgrowth of what is cla.s.sed as woman's work in the primitive barbarian community.

The work of the men in the lower barbarian culture is no less indispensable to the life of the group than the work done by the women.

It may even be that the men's work contributes as much to the food supply and the other necessary consumption of the group. Indeed, so obvious is this "productive" character of the men's work that in the conventional economic writings the hunter's work is taken as the type of primitive industry. But such is not the barbarian's sense of the matter.

In his own eyes he is not a labourer, and he is not to be cla.s.sed with the women in this respect; nor is his effort to be cla.s.sed with the women's drudgery, as labour or industry, in such a sense as to admit of its being confounded with the latter. There is in all barbarian communities a profound sense of the disparity between man's and woman's work. His work may conduce to the maintenance of the group, but it is felt that it does so through an excellence and an efficacy of a kind that cannot without derogation be compared with the uneventful diligence of the women.

At a farther step backward in the cultural scale--among savage groups--the differentiation of employments is still less elaborate and the invidious distinction between cla.s.ses and employments is less consistent and less rigorous. Unequivocal instances of a primitive savage culture are hard to find. Few of these groups or communities that are cla.s.sed as "savage" show no traces of regression from a more advanced cultural stage. But there are groups--some of them apparently not the result of retrogression--which show the traits of primitive savagery with some fidelity. Their culture differs from that of the barbarian communities in the absence of a leisure cla.s.s and the absence, in great measure, of the animus or spiritual att.i.tude on which the inst.i.tution of a leisure cla.s.s rests. These communities of primitive savages in which there is no hierarchy of economic cla.s.ses make up but a small and inconspicuous fraction of the human race. As good an instance of this phase of culture as may be had is afforded by the tribes of the Andamans, or by the Todas of the Nilgiri Hills. The scheme of life of these groups at the time of their earliest contact with Europeans seems to have been nearly typical, so far as regards the absence of a leisure cla.s.s. As a further instance might be cited the Ainu of Yezo, and, more doubtfully, also some Bushman and Eskimo groups. Some Pueblo communities are less confidently to be included in the same cla.s.s. Most, if not all, of the communities here cited may well be cases of degeneration from a higher barbarism, rather than bearers of a culture that has never risen above its present level. If so, they are for the present purpose to be taken with the allowance, but they may serve none the less as evidence to the same effect as if they were really "primitive" populations.

These communities that are without a defined leisure cla.s.s resemble one another also in certain other features of their social structure and manner of life. They are small groups and of a simple (archaic) structure; they are commonly peaceable and sedentary; they are poor; and individual owners.h.i.+p is not a dominant feature of their economic system.

At the same time it does not follow that these are the smallest of existing communities, or that their social structure is in all respects the least differentiated; nor does the cla.s.s necessarily include all primitive communities which have no defined system of individual owners.h.i.+p. But it is to be noted that the cla.s.s seems to include the most peaceable--perhaps all the characteristically peaceable--primitive groups of men. Indeed, the most notable trait common to members of such communities is a certain amiable inefficiency when confronted with force or fraud.

The evidence afforded by the usages and cultural traits of communities at a low stage of development indicates that the inst.i.tution of a leisure cla.s.s has emerged gradually during the transition from primitive savagery to barbarism; or more precisely, during the transition from a peaceable to a consistently warlike habit of life. The conditions apparently necessary to its emergence in a consistent form are: (1) the community must be of a predatory habit of life (war or the hunting of large game or both); that is to say, the men, who const.i.tute the inchoate leisure cla.s.s in these cases, must be habituated to the infliction of injury by force and stratagem; (2) subsistence must be obtainable on sufficiently easy terms to admit of the exemption of a considerable portion of the community from steady application to a routine of labour. The inst.i.tution of leisure cla.s.s is the outgrowth of an early discrimination between employments, according to which some employments are worthy and others unworthy. Under this ancient distinction the worthy employments are those which may be cla.s.sed as exploit; unworthy are those necessary everyday employments into which no appreciable element of exploit enters.

This distinction has but little obvious significance in a modern industrial community, and it has, therefore, received but slight attention at the hands of economic writers. When viewed in the light of that modern common sense which has guided economic discussion, it seems formal and insubstantial. But it persists with great tenacity as a commonplace preconception even in modern life, as is shown, for instance, by our habitual aversion to menial employments. It is a distinction of a personal kind--of superiority and inferiority. In the earlier stages of culture, when the personal force of the individual counted more immediately and obviously in shaping the course of events, the element of exploit counted for more in the everyday scheme of life.

Interest centred about this fact to a greater degree. Consequently a distinction proceeding on this ground seemed more imperative and more definitive then than is the case to-day. As a fact in the sequence of development, therefore, the distinction is a substantial one and rests on sufficiently valid and cogent grounds.

The ground on which a discrimination between facts is habitually made changes as the interest from which the facts are habitually viewed changes. Those features of the facts at hand are salient and substantial upon which the dominant interest of the time throws its light. Any given ground of distinction will seem insubstantial to any one who habitually apprehends the facts in question from a different point of view and values them for a different purpose. The habit of distinguis.h.i.+ng and cla.s.sifying the various purposes and directions of activity prevails of necessity always and everywhere; for it is indispensable in reaching a working theory or scheme of life. The particular point of view, or the particular characteristic that is pitched upon as definitive in the cla.s.sification of the facts of life depends upon the interest from which a discrimination of the facts is sought. The grounds of discrimination, and the norm of procedure in cla.s.sifying the facts, therefore, progressively change as the growth of culture proceeds; for the end for which the facts of life are apprehended changes, and the point of view consequently changes also. So that what are recognised as the salient and decisive features of a cla.s.s of activities or of a social cla.s.s at one stage of culture will not retain the same relative importance for the purposes of cla.s.sification at any subsequent stage.

But the change of standards and points of view is gradual only, and it seldom results in the subversion or entire suppression of a standpoint once accepted. A distinction is still habitually made between industrial and non-industrial occupations; and this modern distinction is a trans.m.u.ted form of the barbarian distinction between exploit and drudgery. Such employments as warfare, politics, public wors.h.i.+p, and public merrymaking, are felt, in the popular apprehension, to differ intrinsically from the labour that has to do with elaborating the material means of life. The precise line of demarcation is not the same as it was in the early barbarian scheme, but the broad distinction has not fallen into disuse.

The tacit, common-sense distinction to-day is, in effect, that any effort is to be accounted industrial only so far as its ultimate purpose is the utilisation of non-human things. The coercive utilisation of man by man is not felt to be an industrial function; but all effort directed to enhance human life by taking advantage of the non-human environment is cla.s.sed together as industrial activity. By the economists who have best retained and adapted the cla.s.sical tradition, man's "power over nature" is currently postulated as the characteristic fact of industrial productivity. This industrial power over nature is taken to include man's power over the life of the beasts and over all the elemental forces. A line is in this way drawn between mankind and brute creation.

In other times and among men imbued with a different body of preconceptions this line is not drawn precisely as we draw it to-day.

In the savage or the barbarian scheme of life it is drawn in a different place and in another way. In all communities under the barbarian culture there is an alert and pervading sense of ant.i.thesis between two comprehensive groups of phenomena, in one of which barbarian man includes himself, and in the other, his victual. There is a felt ant.i.thesis between economic and non-economic phenomena, but it is not conceived in the modern fas.h.i.+on; it lies not between man and brute creation, but between animate and inert things.

It may be an excess of caution at this day to explain that the barbarian notion which it is here intended to convey by the term "animate" is not the same as would be conveyed by the word "living". The term does not cover all living things, and it does cover a great many others. Such a striking natural phenomenon as a storm, a disease, a waterfall, are recognised as "animate"; while fruits and herbs, and even inconspicuous animals, such as house-flies, maggots, lemmings, sheep, are not ordinarily apprehended as "animate" except when taken collectively.

As here used the term does not necessarily imply an indwelling soul or spirit. The concept includes such things as in the apprehension of the animistic savage or barbarian are formidable by virtue of a real or imputed habit of initiating action. This category comprises a large number and range of natural objects and phenomena. Such a distinction between the inert and the active is still present in the habits of thought of unreflecting persons, and it still profoundly affects the prevalent theory of human life and of natural processes; but it does not pervade our daily life to the extent or with the far-reaching practical consequences that are apparent at earlier stages of culture and belief.

To the mind of the barbarian, the elaboration and utilisation of what is afforded by inert nature is activity on quite a different plane from his dealings with "animate" things and forces. The line of demarcation may be vague and s.h.i.+fting, but the broad distinction is sufficiently real and cogent to influence the barbarian scheme of life. To the cla.s.s of things apprehended as animate, the barbarian fancy imputes an unfolding of activity directed to some end. It is this teleological unfolding of activity that const.i.tutes any object or phenomenon an "animate" fact.

Wherever the unsophisticated savage or barbarian meets with activity that is at all obtrusive, he construes it in the only terms that are ready to hand--the terms immediately given in his consciousness of his own actions. Activity is, therefore, a.s.similated to human action, and active objects are in so far a.s.similated to the human agent. Phenomena of this character--especially those whose behaviour is notably formidable or baffling--have to be met in a different spirit and with proficiency of a different kind from what is required in dealing with inert things. To deal successfully with such phenomena is a work of exploit rather than of industry. It is an a.s.sertion of prowess, not of diligence.

Under the guidance of this naive discrimination between the inert and the animate, the activities of the primitive social group tend to fall into two cla.s.ses, which would in modern phrase be called exploit and industry. Industry is effort that goes to create a new thing, with a new purpose given it by the fas.h.i.+oning hand of its maker out of pa.s.sive ("brute") material; while exploit, so far as it results in an outcome useful to the agent, is the conversion to his own ends of energies previously directed to some other end by an other agent. We still speak of "brute matter" with something of the barbarian's realisation of a profound significance in the term.

The distinction between exploit and drudgery coincides with a difference between the s.e.xes. The s.e.xes differ, not only in stature and muscular force, but perhaps even more decisively in temperament, and this must early have given rise to a corresponding division of labour. The general range of activities that come under the head of exploit falls to the males as being the stouter, more ma.s.sive, better capable of a sudden and violent strain, and more readily inclined to self a.s.sertion, active emulation, and aggression. The difference in ma.s.s, in physiological character, and in temperament may be slight among the members of the primitive group; it appears, in fact, to be relatively slight and inconsequential in some of the more archaic communities with which we are acquainted--as for instance the tribes of the Andamans. But so soon as a differentiation of function has well begun on the lines marked out by this difference in physique and animus, the original difference between the s.e.xes will itself widen. A c.u.mulative process of selective adaptation to the new distribution of employments will set in, especially if the habitat or the fauna with which the group is in contact is such as to call for a considerable exercise of the st.u.r.dier virtues. The habitual pursuit of large game requires more of the manly qualities of ma.s.siveness, agility, and ferocity, and it can therefore scarcely fail to hasten and widen the differentiation of functions between the s.e.xes. And so soon as the group comes into hostile contact with other groups, the divergence of function will take on the developed form of a distinction between exploit and industry.

In such a predatory group of hunters it comes to be the able-bodied men's office to fight and hunt. The women do what other work there is to do--other members who are unfit for man's work being for this purpose cla.s.sed with women. But the men's hunting and fighting are both of the same general character. Both are of a predatory nature; the warrior and the hunter alike reap where they have not strewn. Their aggressive a.s.sertion of force and sagacity differs obviously from the women's a.s.siduous and uneventful shaping of materials; it is not to be accounted productive labour but rather an acquisition of substance by seizure.

Such being the barbarian man's work, in its best development and widest divergence from women's work, any effort that does not involve an a.s.sertion of prowess comes to be unworthy of the man. As the tradition gains consistency, the common sense of the community erects it into a canon of conduct; so that no employment and no acquisition is morally possible to the self respecting man at this cultural stage, except such as proceeds on the basis of prowess--force or fraud. When the predatory habit of life has been settled upon the group by long habituation, it becomes the able-bodied man's accredited office in the social economy to kill, to destroy such compet.i.tors in the struggle for existence as attempt to resist or elude him, to overcome and reduce to subservience those alien forces that a.s.sert themselves refractorily in the environment. So tenaciously and with such nicety is this theoretical distinction between exploit and drudgery adhered to that in many hunting tribes the man must not bring home the game which he has killed, but must send his woman to perform that baser office.

As has already been indicated, the distinction between exploit and drudgery is an invidious distinction between employments. Those employments which are to be cla.s.sed as exploit are worthy, honourable, n.o.ble; other employments, which do not contain this element of exploit, and especially those which imply subservience or submission, are unworthy, debasing, ign.o.ble. The concept of dignity, worth, or honour, as applied either to persons or conduct, is of first-rate consequence in the development of cla.s.ses and of cla.s.s distinctions, and it is therefore necessary to say something of its derivation and meaning. Its psychological ground may be indicated in outline as follows.

As a matter of selective necessity, man is an agent. He is, in his own apprehension, a centre of unfolding impulsive activity--"teleological"

activity. He is an agent seeking in every act the accomplishment of some concrete, objective, impersonal end. By force of his being such an agent he is possessed of a taste for effective work, and a distaste for futile effort. He has a sense of the merit of serviceability or efficiency and of the demerit of futility, waste, or incapacity. This apt.i.tude or propensity may be called the instinct of workmans.h.i.+p. Wherever the circ.u.mstances or traditions of life lead to an habitual comparison of one person with another in point of efficiency, the instinct of workmans.h.i.+p works out in an emulative or invidious comparison of persons. The extent to which this result follows depends in some considerable degree on the temperament of the population. In any community where such an invidious comparison of persons is habitually made, visible success becomes an end sought for its own utility as a basis of esteem. Esteem is gained and dispraise is avoided by putting one's efficiency in evidence. The result is that the instinct of workmans.h.i.+p works out in an emulative demonstration of force.

During that primitive phase of social development, when the community is still habitually peaceable, perhaps sedentary, and without a developed system of individual owners.h.i.+p, the efficiency of the individual can be shown chiefly and most consistently in some employment that goes to further the life of the group. What emulation of an economic kind there is between the members of such a group will be chiefly emulation in industrial serviceability. At the same time the incentive to emulation is not strong, nor is the scope for emulation large.

When the community pa.s.ses from peaceable savagery to a predatory phase of life, the conditions of emulation change. The opportunity and the incentive to emulate increase greatly in scope and urgency. The activity of the men more and more takes on the character of exploit; and an invidious comparison of one hunter or warrior with another grows continually easier and more habitual. Tangible evidences of prowess--trophies--find a place in men's habits of thought as an essential feature of the paraphernalia of life. Booty, trophies of the chase or of the raid, come to be prized as evidence of pre-eminent force. Aggression becomes the accredited form of action, and booty serves as prima facie evidence of successful aggression. As accepted at this cultural stage, the accredited, worthy form of self-a.s.sertion is contest; and useful articles or services obtained by seizure or compulsion, serve as a conventional evidence of successful contest.

Therefore, by contrast, the obtaining of goods by other methods than seizure comes to be accounted unworthy of man in his best estate. The performance of productive work, or employment in personal service, falls under the same odium for the same reason. An invidious distinction in this way arises between exploit and acquisition on the other hand.

Labour acquires a character of irksomeness by virtue of the indignity imputed to it.

With the primitive barbarian, before the simple content of the notion has been obscured by its own ramifications and by a secondary growth of cognate ideas, "honourable" seems to connote nothing else than a.s.sertion of superior force. "Honourable" is "formidable"; "worthy" is "prepotent". A honorific act is in the last a.n.a.lysis little if anything else than a recognised successful act of aggression; and where aggression means conflict with men and beasts, the activity which comes to be especially and primarily honourable is the a.s.sertion of the strong hand. The naive, archaic habit of construing all manifestations of force in terms of personality or "will power" greatly fortifies this conventional exaltation of the strong hand. Honorific epithets, in vogue among barbarian tribes as well as among peoples of a more advance culture, commonly bear the stamp of this unsophisticated sense of honour. Epithets and t.i.tles used in addressing chieftains, and in the propitiation of kings and G.o.ds, very commonly impute a propensity for overbearing violence and an irresistible devastating force to the person who is to be propitiated. This holds true to an extent also in the more civilised communities of the present day. The predilection shown in heraldic devices for the more rapacious beasts and birds of prey goes to enforce the same view.

Under this common-sense barbarian appreciation of worth or honour, the taking of life--the killing of formidable compet.i.tors, whether brute or human--is honourable in the highest degree. And this high office of slaughter, as an expression of the slayer's prepotence, casts a glamour of worth over every act of slaughter and over all the tools and accessories of the act. Arms are honourable, and the use of them, even in seeking the life of the meanest creatures of the fields, becomes a honorific employment. At the same time, employment in industry becomes correspondingly odious, and, in the common-sense apprehension, the handling of the tools and implements of industry falls beneath the dignity of able-bodied men. Labour becomes irksome.

It is here a.s.sumed that in the sequence of cultural evolution primitive groups of men have pa.s.sed from an initial peaceable stage to a subsequent stage at which fighting is the avowed and characteristic employment of the group. But it is not implied that there has been an abrupt transition from unbroken peace and good-will to a later or higher phase of life in which the fact of combat occurs for the first time.

Neither is it implied that all peaceful industry disappears on the transition to the predatory phase of culture. Some fighting, it is safe to say, would be met with at any early stage of social development.

Fights would occur with more or less frequency through s.e.xual compet.i.tion. The known habits of primitive groups, as well as the habits of the anthropoid apes, argue to that effect, and the evidence from the well-known promptings of human nature enforces the same view.

It may therefore be objected that there can have been no such initial stage of peaceable life as is here a.s.sumed. There is no point in cultural evolution prior to which fighting does not occur. But the point in question is not as to the occurrence of combat, occasional or sporadic, or even more or less frequent and habitual; it is a question as to the occurrence of an habitual; it is a question as to the occurrence of an habitual bellicose frame of mind--a prevalent habit of judging facts and events from the point of view of the fight. The predatory phase of culture is attained only when the predatory att.i.tude has become the habitual and accredited spiritual att.i.tude for the members of the group; when the fight has become the dominant note in the current theory of life; when the common-sense appreciation of men and things has come to be an appreciation with a view to combat.

The substantial difference between the peaceable and the predatory phase of culture, therefore, is a spiritual difference, not a mechanical one.

The change in spiritual att.i.tude is the outgrowth of a change in the material facts of the life of the group, and it comes on gradually as the material circ.u.mstances favourable to a predatory att.i.tude supervene.

The inferior limit of the predatory culture is an industrial limit.

Predation can not become the habitual, conventional resource of any group or any cla.s.s until industrial methods have been developed to such a degree of efficiency as to leave a margin worth fighting for, above the subsistence of those engaged in getting a living. The transition from peace to predation therefore depends on the growth of technical knowledge and the use of tools. A predatory culture is similarly impracticable in early times, until weapons have been developed to such a point as to make man a formidable animal. The early development of tools and of weapons is of course the same fact seen from two different points of view.

The life of a given group would be characterised as peaceable so long as habitual recourse to combat has not brought the fight into the foreground in men's every day thoughts, as a dominant feature of the life of man. A group may evidently attain such a predatory att.i.tude with a greater or less degree of completeness, so that its scheme of life and canons of conduct may be controlled to a greater or less extent by the predatory animus. The predatory phase of culture is therefore conceived to come on gradually, through a c.u.mulative growth of predatory apt.i.tudes habits, and traditions this growth being due to a change in the circ.u.mstances of the group's life, of such a kind as to develop and conserve those traits of human nature and those traditions and norms of conduct that make for a predatory rather than a peaceable life.

The evidence for the hypothesis that there has been such a peaceable stage of primitive culture is in great part drawn from psychology rather than from ethnology, and cannot be detailed here. It will be recited in part in a later chapter, in discussing the survival of archaic traits of human nature under the modern culture.

Chapter Two -- Pecuniary Emulation

In the sequence of cultural evolution the emergence of a leisure cla.s.s coincides with the beginning of owners.h.i.+p. This is necessarily the case, for these two inst.i.tutions result from the same set of economic forces.

In the inchoate phase of their development they are but different aspects of the same general facts of social structure.

It is as elements of social structure--conventional facts--that leisure and owners.h.i.+p are matters of interest for the purpose in hand. An habitual neglect of work does not const.i.tute a leisure cla.s.s; neither does the mechanical fact of use and consumption const.i.tute owners.h.i.+p.

The present inquiry, therefore, is not concerned with the beginning of indolence, nor with the beginning of the appropriation of useful articles to individual consumption. The point in question is the origin and nature of a conventional leisure cla.s.s on the one hand and the beginnings of individual owners.h.i.+p as a conventional right or equitable claim on the other hand.

The early differentiation out of which the distinction between a leisure and a working cla.s.s arises is a division maintained between men's and women's work in the lower stages of barbarism. Likewise the earliest form of owners.h.i.+p is an owners.h.i.+p of the women by the able bodied men of the community. The facts may be expressed in more general terms, and truer to the import of the barbarian theory of life, by saying that it is an owners.h.i.+p of the woman by the man.

Click Like and comment to support us!

RECENTLY UPDATED NOVELS

About Theory of the Leisure Class Part 1 novel

You're reading Theory of the Leisure Class by Author(s): Thorstein Veblen. This novel has been translated and updated at LightNovelsOnl.com and has already 554 views. And it would be great if you choose to read and follow your favorite novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest novels, a novel list updates everyday and free. LightNovelsOnl.com is a very smart website for reading novels online, friendly on mobile. If you have any questions, please do not hesitate to contact us at [email protected] or just simply leave your comment so we'll know how to make you happy.