LightNovesOnl.com

Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 26

Summa Theologica - LightNovelsOnl.com

You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.

as the Philosopher says (Phys. iii). Moreover, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xii) that "whatever is comprehended by knowledge, is bounded by the comprehension of the knower." Now infinite things have no boundary. Therefore they cannot be comprehended by the knowledge of G.o.d.

Obj. 2: Further, if we say that things infinite in themselves are finite in G.o.d's knowledge, against this it may be urged that the essence of the infinite is that it is untraversable, and the finite that it is traversable, as said in _Phys._ iii. But the infinite is not traversable either by the finite or by the infinite, as is proved in Phys. vi. Therefore the infinite cannot be bounded by the finite, nor even by the infinite; and so the infinite cannot be finite in G.o.d's knowledge, which is infinite.

Obj. 3: Further, the knowledge of G.o.d is the measure of what is known. But it is contrary to the essence of the infinite that it be measured. Therefore infinite things cannot be known by G.o.d.

_On the contrary,_ Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xii), "Although we cannot number the infinite, nevertheless it can be comprehended by Him whose knowledge has no bounds."

_I answer that,_ Since G.o.d knows not only things actual but also things possible to Himself or to created things, as shown above (A.

9), and as these must be infinite, it must be held that He knows infinite things. Although the knowledge of vision which has relation only to things that are, or will be, or were, is not of infinite things, as some say, for we do not say that the world is eternal, nor that generation and movement will go on for ever, so that individuals be infinitely multiplied; yet, if we consider more attentively, we must hold that G.o.d knows infinite things even by the knowledge of vision. For G.o.d knows even the thoughts and affections of hearts, which will be multiplied to infinity as rational creatures go on for ever.

The reason of this is to be found in the fact that the knowledge of every knower is measured by the mode of the form which is the principle of knowledge. For the sensible image in sense is the likeness of only one individual thing, and can give the knowledge of only one individual. But the intelligible species of our intellect is the likeness of the thing as regards its specific nature, which is partic.i.p.able by infinite particulars; hence our intellect by the intelligible species of man in a certain way knows infinite men; not however as distinguished from each other, but as communicating in the nature of the species; and the reason is because the intelligible species of our intellect is the likeness of man not as to the individual principles, but as to the principles of the species. On the other hand, the divine essence, whereby the divine intellect understands, is a sufficing likeness of all things that are, or can be, not only as regards the universal principles, but also as regards the principles proper to each one, as shown above. Hence it follows that the knowledge of G.o.d extends to infinite things, even as distinct from each other.

Reply Obj. 1: The idea of the infinite pertains to quant.i.ty, as the Philosopher says (Phys. i). But the idea of quant.i.ty implies the order of parts. Therefore to know the infinite according to the mode of the infinite is to know part after part; and in this way the infinite cannot be known; for whatever quant.i.ty of parts be taken, there will always remain something else outside. But G.o.d does not know the infinite or infinite things, as if He enumerated part after part; since He knows all things simultaneously, and not successively, as said above (A. 7). Hence there is nothing to prevent Him from knowing infinite things.

Reply Obj. 2: Transition imports a certain succession of parts; and hence it is that the infinite cannot be traversed by the finite, nor by the infinite. But equality suffices for comprehension, because that is said to be comprehended which has nothing outside the comprehender. Hence it is not against the idea of the infinite to be comprehended by the infinite. And so, what is infinite in itself can be called finite to the knowledge of G.o.d as comprehended; but not as if it were traversable.

Reply Obj. 3: The knowledge of G.o.d is the measure of things, not quant.i.tatively, for the infinite is not subject to this kind of measure; but it is the measure of the essence and truth of things.

For everything has truth of nature according to the degree in which it imitates the knowledge of G.o.d, as the thing made by art agrees with the art. Granted, however, an actually infinite number of things, for instance, an infinitude of men, or an infinitude in continuous quant.i.ty, as an infinitude of air, as some of the ancients held; yet it is manifest that these would have a determinate and finite being, because their being would be limited to some determinate nature. Hence they would be measurable as regards the knowledge of G.o.d.

_______________________

THIRTEENTH ARTICLE [I, Q. 14, Art. 13]

Whether the Knowledge of G.o.d Is of Future Contingent Things?

Objection 1: It seems that the knowledge of G.o.d is not of future contingent things. For from a necessary cause proceeds a necessary effect. But the knowledge of G.o.d is the cause of things known, as said above (A. 8). Since therefore that knowledge is necessary, what He knows must also be necessary. Therefore the knowledge of G.o.d is not of contingent things.

Obj. 2: Further, every conditional proposition of which the antecedent is absolutely necessary must have an absolutely necessary consequent. For the antecedent is to the consequent as principles are to the conclusion: and from necessary principles only a necessary conclusion can follow, as is proved in _Poster._ i. But this is a true conditional proposition, "If G.o.d knew that this thing will be, it will be," for the knowledge of G.o.d is only of true things. Now the antecedent conditional of this is absolutely necessary, because it is eternal, and because it is signified as past. Therefore the consequent is also absolutely necessary. Therefore whatever G.o.d knows, is necessary; and so the knowledge of G.o.d is not of contingent things.

Obj. 3: Further, everything known by G.o.d must necessarily be, because even what we ourselves know, must necessarily be; and, of course, the knowledge of G.o.d is much more certain than ours. But no future contingent things must necessarily be. Therefore no contingent future thing is known by G.o.d.

_On the contrary,_ It is written (Ps. 32:15), "He Who hath made the hearts of every one of them; Who understandeth all their works," i.e.

of men. Now the works of men are contingent, being subject to free will. Therefore G.o.d knows future contingent things.

_I answer that,_ Since as was shown above (A. 9), G.o.d knows all things; not only things actual but also things possible to Him and creature; and since some of these are future contingent to us, it follows that G.o.d knows future contingent things.

In evidence of this, we must consider that a contingent thing can be considered in two ways; first, in itself, in so far as it is now in act: and in this sense it is not considered as future, but as present; neither is it considered as contingent (as having reference) to one of two terms, but as determined to one; and on account of this it can be infallibly the object of certain knowledge, for instance to the sense of sight, as when I see that Socrates is sitting down. In another way a contingent thing can be considered as it is in its cause; and in this way it is considered as future, and as a contingent thing not yet determined to one; forasmuch as a contingent cause has relation to opposite things: and in this sense a contingent thing is not subject to any certain knowledge. Hence, whoever knows a contingent effect in its cause only, has merely a conjectural knowledge of it. Now G.o.d knows all contingent things not only as they are in their causes, but also as each one of them is actually in itself. And although contingent things become actual successively, nevertheless G.o.d knows contingent things not successively, as they are in their own being, as we do but simultaneously. The reason is because His knowledge is measured by eternity, as is also His being; and eternity being simultaneously whole comprises all time, as said above (Q. 10, A. 2). Hence all things that are in time are present to G.o.d from eternity, not only because He has the types of things present within Him, as some say; but because His glance is carried from eternity over all things as they are in their presentiality.

Hence it is manifest that contingent things are infallibly known by G.o.d, inasmuch as they are subject to the divine sight in their presentiality; yet they are future contingent things in relation to their own causes.

Reply Obj. 1: Although the supreme cause is necessary, the effect may be contingent by reason of the proximate contingent cause; just as the germination of a plant is contingent by reason of the proximate contingent cause, although the movement of the sun which is the first cause, is necessary. So likewise things known by G.o.d are contingent on account of their proximate causes, while the knowledge of G.o.d, which is the first cause, is necessary.

Reply Obj. 2: Some say that this antecedent, "G.o.d knew this contingent to be future," is not necessary, but contingent; because, although it is past, still it imports relation to the future. This however does not remove necessity from it; for whatever has had relation to the future, must have had it, although the future sometimes does not follow. On the other hand some say that this antecedent is contingent, because it is a compound of necessary and contingent; as this saying is contingent, "Socrates is a white man."

But this also is to no purpose; for when we say, "G.o.d knew this contingent to be future," contingent is used here only as the matter of the word, and not as the chief part of the proposition. Hence its contingency or necessity has no reference to the necessity or contingency of the proposition, or to its being true or false. For it may be just as true that I said a man is an a.s.s, as that I said Socrates runs, or G.o.d is: and the same applies to necessary and contingent. Hence it must be said that this antecedent is absolutely necessary. Nor does it follow, as some say, that the consequent is absolutely necessary, because the antecedent is the remote cause of the consequent, which is contingent by reason of the proximate cause.

But this is to no purpose. For the conditional would be false were its antecedent the remote necessary cause, and the consequent a contingent effect; as, for example, if I said, "if the sun moves, the gra.s.s will grow."

Therefore we must reply otherwise; that when the antecedent contains anything belonging to an act of the soul, the consequent must be taken not as it is in itself, but as it is in the soul: for the existence of a thing in itself is different from the existence of a thing in the soul. For example, when I say, "What the soul understands is immaterial," this is to be understood that it is immaterial as it is in the intellect, not as it is in itself.

Likewise if I say, "If G.o.d knew anything, it will be," the consequent must be understood as it is subject to the divine knowledge, i.e. as it is in its presentiality. And thus it is necessary, as also is the antecedent: "For everything that is, while it is, must be necessarily be," as the Philosopher says in _Peri Herm._ i.

Reply Obj. 3: Things reduced to act in time, as known by us successively in time, but by G.o.d (are known) in eternity, which is above time. Whence to us they cannot be certain, forasmuch as we know future contingent things as such; but (they are certain) to G.o.d alone, whose understanding is in eternity above time. Just as he who goes along the road, does not see those who come after him; whereas he who sees the whole road from a height, sees at once all travelling by the way. Hence what is known by us must be necessary, even as it is in itself; for what is future contingent in itself, cannot be known by us. Whereas what is known by G.o.d must be necessary according to the mode in which they are subject to the divine knowledge, as already stated, but not absolutely as considered in their own causes.

Hence also this proposition, "Everything known by G.o.d must necessarily be," is usually distinguished; for this may refer to the thing, or to the saying. If it refers to the thing, it is divided and false; for the sense is, "Everything which G.o.d knows is necessary."

If understood of the saying, it is composite and true; for the sense is, "This proposition, 'that which is known by G.o.d is' is necessary."

Now some urge an objection and say that this distinction holds good with regard to forms that are separable from the subject; thus if I said, "It is possible for a white thing to be black," it is false as applied to the saying, and true as applied to the thing: for a thing which is white, can become black; whereas this saying, "a white thing is black" can never be true. But in forms that are inseparable from the subject, this distinction does not hold, for instance, if I said, "A black crow can be white"; for in both senses it is false. Now to be known by G.o.d is inseparable from the thing; for what is known by G.o.d cannot be known. This objection, however, would hold if these words "that which is known" implied any disposition inherent to the subject; but since they import an act of the knower, something can be attributed to the thing known, in itself (even if it always be known), which is not attributed to it in so far as it stands under actual knowledge; thus material existence is attributed to a stone in itself, which is not attributed to it inasmuch as it is known.

_______________________

FOURTEENTH ARTICLE [I, Q. 14, Art. 14]

Whether G.o.d Knows Enunciable Things?

Objection 1: It seems that G.o.d does not know enunciable things. For to know enunciable things belongs to our intellect as it composes and divides. But in the divine intellect, there is no composition.

Therefore G.o.d does not know enunciable things.

Obj. 2: Further, every kind of knowledge is made through some likeness. But in G.o.d there is no likeness of enunciable things, since He is altogether simple. Therefore G.o.d does not know enunciable things.

_On the contrary,_ It is written: "The Lord knoweth the thoughts of men"

(Ps. 93:11). But enunciable things are contained in the thoughts of men. Therefore G.o.d knows enunciable things.

_I answer that,_ Since it is in the power of our intellect to form enunciations, and since G.o.d knows whatever is in His own power or in that of creatures, as said above (A. 9), it follows of necessity that G.o.d knows all enunciations that can be formed.

Now just as He knows material things immaterially, and composite things simply, so likewise He knows enunciable things not after the manner of enunciable things, as if in His intellect there were composition or division of enunciations; for He knows each thing by simple intelligence, by understanding the essence of each thing; as if we by the very fact that we understand what man is, were to understand all that can be predicated of man. This, however, does not happen in our intellect, which discourses from one thing to another, forasmuch as the intelligible species represents one thing in such a way as not to represent another. Hence when we understand what man is, we do not forthwith understand other things which belong to him, but we understand them one by one, according to a certain succession. On this account the things we understand as separated, we must reduce to one by way of composition or division, by forming an enunciation. Now the species of the divine intellect, which is G.o.d's essence, suffices to represent all things. Hence by understanding His essence, G.o.d knows the essences of all things, and also whatever can be accidental to them.

Reply Obj. 1: This objection would avail if G.o.d knew enunciable things after the manner of enunciable things.

Reply Obj. 2: Enunciatory composition signifies some existence of a thing; and thus G.o.d by His existence, which is His essence, is the similitude of all those things which are signified by enunciation.

_______________________

FIFTEENTH ARTICLE [I, Q. 14, Art. 15]

Whether the Knowledge of G.o.d Is Variable?

Objection 1: It seems that the knowledge of G.o.d is variable. For knowledge is related to what is knowable. But whatever imports relation to the creature is applied to G.o.d from time, and varies according to the variation of creatures. Therefore the knowledge of G.o.d is variable according to the variation of creatures.

Obj. 2: Further, whatever G.o.d can make, He can know. But G.o.d can make more than He does. Therefore He can know more than He knows.

Thus His knowledge can vary according to increase and diminution.

Obj. 3: Further, G.o.d knew that Christ would be born. But He does not know now that Christ will be born; because Christ is not to be born in the future. Therefore G.o.d does not know everything He once knew; and thus the knowledge of G.o.d is variable.

_On the contrary,_ It is said, that in G.o.d "there is no change nor shadow of alteration" (James 1:17).

_I answer that,_ Since the knowledge of G.o.d is His substance, as is clear from the foregoing (A. 4), just as His substance is altogether immutable, as shown above (Q. 9, A. 1), so His knowledge likewise must be altogether invariable.

Reply Obj. 1: "Lord", "Creator" and the like, import relations to creatures in so far as they are in themselves. But the knowledge of G.o.d imports relation to creatures in so far as they are in G.o.d; because everything is actually understood according as it is in the one who understands. Now created things are in G.o.d in an invariable manner; while they exist variably in themselves. We may also say that "Lord", "Creator" and the like, import the relations consequent upon the acts which are understood as terminating in the creatures themselves, as they are in themselves; and thus these relations are attributed to G.o.d variously, according to the variation of creatures.

But "knowledge" and "love," and the like, import relations consequent upon the acts which are understood to be in G.o.d; and therefore these are predicated of G.o.d in an invariable manner.

Reply Obj. 2: G.o.d knows also what He can make, and does not make.

Hence from the fact that He can make more than He makes, it does not follow that He can know more than He knows, unless this be referred to the knowledge of vision, according to which He is said to know those things which are in act in some period of time. But from the fact that He knows some things might be which are not, or that some things might not be which are, it does not follow that His knowledge is variable, but rather that He knows the variability of things. If, however, anything existed which G.o.d did not previously know, and afterwards knew, then His knowledge would be variable. But this could not be; for whatever is, or can be in any period of time, is known by G.o.d in His eternity. Therefore from the fact that a thing exists in some period of time, it follows that it is known by G.o.d from eternity. Therefore it cannot be granted that G.o.d can know more than He knows; because such a proposition implies that first of all He did not know, and then afterwards knew.

Reply Obj. 3: The ancient Nominalists said that it was the same thing to say "Christ is born" and "will be born" and "was born"; because the same thing is signified by these three--viz. the nativity of Christ. Therefore it follows, they said, that whatever G.o.d knew, He knows; because now He knows that Christ is born, which means the same thing as that Christ will be born. This opinion, however, is false; both because the diversity in the parts of a sentence causes a diversity of enunciations; and because it would follow that a proposition which is true once would be always true; which is contrary to what the Philosopher lays down (Categor. iii) when he says that this sentence, "Socrates sits," is true when he is sitting, and false when he rises up. Therefore, it must be conceded that this proposition is not true, "Whatever G.o.d knew He knows," if referred to enunciable propositions. But because of this, it does not follow that the knowledge of G.o.d is variable. For as it is without variation in the divine knowledge that G.o.d knows one and the same thing sometime to be, and sometime not to be, so it is without variation in the divine knowledge that G.o.d knows an enunciable proposition is sometime true, and sometime false. The knowledge of G.o.d, however, would be variable if He knew enunciable things by way of enunciation, by composition and division, as occurs in our intellect. Hence our knowledge varies either as regards truth and falsity, for example, if when either as regards truth and falsity, for example, if when a thing suffers change we retained the same opinion about it; or as regards diverse opinions, as if we first thought that anyone was sitting, and afterwards thought that he was not sitting; neither of which can be in G.o.d.

_______________________

Click Like and comment to support us!

RECENTLY UPDATED NOVELS

About Summa Theologica Part I (Prima Pars) Part 26 novel

You're reading Summa Theologica by Author(s): Saint Aquinas Thomas. This novel has been translated and updated at LightNovelsOnl.com and has already 1047 views. And it would be great if you choose to read and follow your favorite novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest novels, a novel list updates everyday and free. LightNovelsOnl.com is a very smart website for reading novels online, friendly on mobile. If you have any questions, please do not hesitate to contact us at [email protected] or just simply leave your comment so we'll know how to make you happy.