What Is This Thing Called Science - LightNovelsOnl.com
You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.
Karl Popper was the most forceful advocate of an alternative to inductivism which I will refer to as "falsificationism". Popper was educated in Vienna in the 1920s, at a time when logical positivism was being articulated by a group of philosophers who became known as the Vienna Circle. One of the most famous of these was Rudolph Carnap, and the clash and debate between his supporters and those of Popper was to be a feature of philosophy of science up until the 1960s. Popper himself tells the story of how he became disenchanted with the idea that science is special because it can be derived from the facts, the more facts the better. He became suspicious of the way in which he saw Freudians and Marxists supporting their theories by interpreting a wide range of instances, of human behaviour or historical change respectively, in terms of their theory and claiming them to be supported on this account. It seemed to Popper that these theories could never go wrong because they_were sufficiently flexible to accommodate any instances of human behaviour or historical change as compatible with their theory. Consequently, although giving the appearance of being powerful theories confirmed by a wide range of facts, they could in fact explain nothing becauo they could rule out nothing. Popper compared this with a famous test of Einstein's theory of general relativity carried out by Eddington in 1919. Einstein's theory had the implication that rays of light should bend as they pa.s.s close to Ma.s.sive objects such as the sun. As a consequence, a star situated beyond the sun should appear displaced from the direction in which it would be observed in the absence of this bending. Eddington sought for this displacement by sighting the star at a time when the light from the sun was blocked out by an eclipse. It transpired that the displacement was observed and Einstein's theory was borne out. But Popper makes the point that it might not have been. By making a specific, testable prediction the general theory of relativity was at risk. It ruled out observations that clashed with that prediction. Popper die l"; the moral that genuine scientific theories, by making definite predictions, rule out a range of observable states of affairs in a way that he considered Freudian and Marxist theory failed to do. He arrived at his key idea that scientific theories are falsifiable.
Falsificationists freely admit that observation is guided by and presupposes theory. They are also happy to abandon any claim implying that theories can be established as true or probably true in the light of observational evidence. Theories are construed as speculative and tentative conjectures or guesses freely created by the human intellect in an attempt to overcome problems encountered by previous theories to give an adequate account of some aspects of the world or universe. Once proposed, speculative theories are to be rigorously and ruthlessly tested by observation and experiment. Theories that fail to stand up to observational and experimenU tests must be eliminated and replaced by further speculative conjectures. Science progresses by trial and error, by conjectures andrefutations. Only the fitfeif theories survive. Although it can never be legitimately said of a theory that it is true, it can hopefully be said that it is the best available; that it is better than anything that has come before. No problems about the characterisation and justification of induction arise for the falsificationists because, according to them, science does not involve induction.
The content of this condensed summary of falsificationism will be filled out in the next two chapters.
A logical point in favour of falsificationism.
According to falsificationism, some theories can be shown to be false by an appeal to the results of observation and experiment. There is a simple, logical point that seems to support the falsificationist here. I have already indicated in chapter 4 that, even if we a.s.sume that true observational statements are available to us in some way, it is never possible to arrive at universal laws and theories by logical deductions on that basis alone. However, it is possible to perfol in logical deductions starting from singular observation statements as premises, to arrive at the falsity of universal laws and theories by logical deduction. For example, if we are given the statement, "A raven which was not black was observed at place x at time t", then it logically follows from this that "All ravens are black" is false. That is, the argument: Premise: A raven, which was not black, was at place x at time t.
Conclusion: Not all ravens are black.
is a logically valid deduction. If the premise is a.s.serted and the conclusion denied, a contradiction is involved. One or two more examples will help ill.u.s.trate this fairly trivial logical point. If it can be established by observation in some test experiment that a ten-kilogram weight and a one-kilogram weight in free fall move downwards at roughly the same speed, then it can be concluded that the claim that bodies fall at speeds proportional to their weight is false. If it can be demonstrated beyond doubt that a ray of light pa.s.sing close to the sun is deflected in a curved path, then it is not the case that light necessarily travels in straight lines.
The falsity of universal statements can be deduced from suitable singular statements. The falsificationist exploits this logical point to the full.
Falsifiability as a criterion for theories.
The falsificationist sees science as a set of hypotheses that are tentatively proposed with the aim of accurately describing or accounting for the behaviour of some aspect of the world or universe. However, not any hypothesis will do. There is one fundamental condition that any hypothesis or system of hypotheses must satisfy if it is to be granted the status of a scientific law or theory. If it is to form part of science, an hypothesis must be falsifiable. Before proceeding any further; it is important to be clear about the falsificationist's usage of the term "falsifiable".
Here are some examples of some simple a.s.sertions that are falsifiable in the sense intended.
It never rains on Wednesdays.
All substances expand when heated.
Heavy objects such as a brick when released near the surface of the earth fall straight downwards if not impeded.
When a ray of light is reflected from a plane mirror, the angle of incidence is equal to the angle of reflection.
a.s.sertion 1 is falsifiable because it can be falsified by observing rain to fall on a Wednesday. a.s.sertion 2 is falsifiable. It can be falsified by an observation statement to the effect that some substance, x, did not expand when heated at time t. Water near its freezing point would serve to falsify 2. Both 1 and 2 are falsifiable and false. a.s.sertions 3 and 4 may be true, for all I know. Nevertheless, they are falsifiable in the sense intended. It is logically possible that the next brick to be relased will "fall" upwards. No logical contradiction is involved in the a.s.sertion, "The brick fell upwards when released", although it may be that no such statement is ever supported by observation. a.s.sertion 4 is falsifiable because a ray of light incident on a mirror at some oblique angle could conceivably be reflected in a direction perpendicular to the mirror. This will never happen if the law of reflection happens to be true, but no logical contradiction would be involved if it did. Both 3 and 4 are falsifiable, e'en though they may be true.
An hypothesis is falsifiable if there exists a logically possible observation statement or set of observation statements that are inconsistent with it, that is, which, if established as true, would falsify the hypothesis.
Here are some examples of statements that do not satisfy this requirement and that are consequently not falsifiable.
Either it is raining or it is not raining.
All points on a Euclidean circle are equidistant from the centre.
Luck is possible in sporting speculation.
No logically possible observation statement could refute 5.
It is true whatever the weather is like. a.s.sertion 6 is necessarily true because of the definition of a Euclidean circle. If points on a circle were not equidistant from some fixed point, then that figure would just not be a Euclidean circle. "All bachelors are unmarried" is unfalsifiable for a similar reason. a.s.sertion 7 is quoted from a horoscope in a newspaper. It typifies the fortune-teller's devious strategy The a.s.sertion is unfalsifiable. It amounts to telling the reader that if he has a bet today he might win, which remains true whether he bets or not, and if he does, whether he wins or not.
Falsificationists demand that scientific hypotheses be falsifiable, in the sense discussed. They insist on this because itis only by ruling out a set of logically possible observation statements that a law or theory is informative. If a statement is unfalsifiable, then the world can have any properties whatsoever, and can behave in any way whatsoever, without conflicting with the statement. Statements 5, 6 and 7, unlike statements 1, 2, 3 and 4, tell us nothing about the world. A scientific law or theory should ideally give us some information about how the world does in fact behave, thereby ruling out ways in which it could (logically) possibly behave but in fact does not. The law "All planets move in ellipses around the sun" is scientific because it claims that planets in fact move in ellipses and rules out orbits that are square or oval. Just because the law makes definite claims about planetary orbits, it has informative content and is falsifiable.
A cursory glarice at some laws that might be regarded as typical components of scientific theories indicates that they satisfy the falsifiability criterion. "Unlike magnetic poles attract each other", "An acid added to a base yields a salt plus water" and similar laws can easily be construed as falsifiable. However, the falsificationist maintains that some theories, while they may superficially appear to have the characteristics of good scientific theories, are in fact only posing as scientific theories because they are not falsifiable and should be rejected. Popper has claimed that some versions at least of Marx's theory of history Freudian psychoa.n.a.lysis and Adlerian psychology suffer from this fault. The point can be ill.u.s.trated by the following caricature of Adlerian psychology.
A fundamental tenet of Adler's theory is that human actions are motivated by feelings of inferiority of some kind. In our caricature, this is supported by the following incident. A man is standing on the bank of a treacherous river at the instant a child falls into the river nearby. The man will either leap into the river in an attempt to save the child or he will not. If he does leap in, the Adlerian responds by indicating how this supports his theory The man obviously needed to overcome his feeling of inferiority by demonstrating that he was brave enough to leap into the river, in spite of the danger. If the man does not leap in, the Adlerian can again claim support for his theory The man was overcoming his feelings of inferiority by demonstrating that he had the strength of will to remain on the bank, unperturbed, while the child drowned.
If this caricature is typical of the way in which Adlerian theory operates, then the theory is not falsifiable. It is consistent with any kind of human behaviour, and just because of that, it tells us nothing about human behaviour. Of course, before Adler's theory can be rejected on these grounds, it would be necessary to investigate the details of the theory rather than a caricature. But there are plenty of social, psychological and religious theories that give rise to the suspicion that in their concern to explain everything they explain nothing. The existence of a loving G.o.d and the occurrence of some disaster can be made compatible by interpreting the disaster as being sent to try us or to punish us, whichever seems most suited to the situation. Many examples of animal behaviour can be seen as evidence supporting the a.s.sertion, "Animals are designed so as best to fulfil the function for which they were intended". Theorists operating in this way are guilty of the fortune-teller's evasion and are subject to the falsificationist's criticism. If a theory is to have informative content, it must run the risk of being falsified.
Degree of falsifiability, clarity and precision.
A good scientific law or theory is falsifiable just because it Makes definite claims about the world. For the falsificationist, ft follows fairly readily from this that the more falsifiable a theory is the better, in some loose sense of more. The more a theory claims, the more potential opportunities there will be for showing that the world does not in fact behave in the way laid down by the theory. A very good theory will be one that makes very wide-ranging claims about the world, and which is consequently highly falsifiable, and is one that resists falsification whenever it is put to the test.
The point can be ill.u.s.trated by means of a trivial example. Consider these laws: Mars moves in an ellipse around the sun.
All planets move in ellipses around their sun.
I take it that it is clear that (b) has a higher status than (a) as a piece of scientific knowledge. Law (b) tells us all that (a) tells us and more besides. Law (b), the preferable law, is more falsifiable than (a). If observations of Mars should turn out to falsify (a), then they would falsify (b) also. Any falsification of (a) will be a falsification of (b), but the reverse is not the case. Observation statements referring to the orbits of Venus, Jupiter, etc. that might conceivably falsify (b) are irrelevant to (a). If we follow Popper and refer to those sets of observation statements that would serve to falsify a law or theory as potential falsifiers of that law or theory, then we can say that the potential falsifiers of (a) form a cla.s.s that is a subcla.s.s of the potential falsifiers of (b). Law (b) is more falsifiable than law (a), which is tantamount to saying that it claims more, that it is the better law.
A less-contrived example involves the relation between Kepler's theory of the solar system and Newton's. Kepler's theory I take to be his three laws of planetary motion. Potential falsifiers of that theory consist of sets of statements referring to planetary positions relative to the sun at specified times. Newton's theory, a better theory that superseded Kepler's, is more corr6hensive. It consists of Newton's laws of motion plus his law of gravitation, the latter a.s.serting that all pairs of bodies in the universe attract each other with a force that varies inversely as the square of their separation. Some of the potential falsifiers of Newton's theory are sets of statements of planetary positions at specified times. But there are many others, including those referring to the behaviour of falling bodies and pendulums, the correlation between the tides and the locations of the sun and moon, and so on. There are many more opportunities for falsifying Newton's theory than for falsifying Kepler's theory And yet, so the falsificationist story goes, Newton's theory was able to resist attempted falsifications, thereby establis.h.i.+ng its superiority over Kepler's.
Highly falsifiable theories should be preferred to less falsifiable ones, then, provided they have not in fact been falsified. The qualification is important for the falsificationist. Theories that have been falsified must be ruthlessly rejected. The enterprise of science involves the proposal of highly falsifiable hypotheses, followed by deliberate and tenacious attempts to falsify them. To quote Popper (1969, p. 231, italics in original): I can therefore gladly admit that falsificationists like myself much prefer an attempt to solve an interesting problem by a bold conjecture, even (and especially) if it soon turns out to be false, to any recital of a sequence of irrelevant truisms. We prefer this because we believe that this is the way in which we can learn from our mistakes; and that in finding that our conjecture was false we shall have learnt much about the truth, and shall have got nearer to the truth.
We learn from our mistakes. Science progresses by trial and error Because of the logical situation that renders the derivation of universal laws and theories from observation statements impossible, but the deduction of their falsity possible, falsifications become the important landmarks, the striking achievements, the major growing-points in science. This somewhat counter-intuitive emphasis of the more extreme falsificationists on the significance of falsifications will be criticised in later chapters.
Because science aims at theories with a large informative content, the falsificationist welcomes the proposal of bold speculative conjectures. Rash speculations are to be encouraged, provided they are falsifiable and provided they are rejected when falsified. This do-or-die att.i.tude crashes with the caution ad Oted by the extreme inductivist. According to the latter, only those theories that can be shown to be true or probably true are to be admitted into science. We should proceed beyond the immediate results of experience only so far as legitimate inductions will take us. The falsificationist, by contrast, recognises the limitation of induction and the subservienee of observation to theory. Nature's secrets can only be revealed with the aid of ingenious and penetrating theories. The greater the number of conjectured theories that are confronted by the realities of the world, and the more speculative those conjectures are, the greater will be the chances of major advances in science. There is no danger in the proliferation of speculative theories because any that are inadequate as descriptions of the world can be ruthlessly eliminated as the result of observational or other tests.
The demand that theories should be highly falsifiable has the attractive consequence that theories should be clearly stated and precise. If a theory is so vaguely stated that it is not clear exactly what it is claiming, then when tested by observation or experiment it can always be interpreted so as to be consistent with the results of those tests. In this way, it can be defended against falsifications. For example, Goethe (1970, p. 295) wrote of electricity that: it is a nothing, a zero, a mere point, which, however, dwells in all apparent existences, and at the same time is the point of origin whence, on the slightest stimulus, a double appearance presents itself, an appearence which only manifests itself to vanish. The conditions under which this manifestation is excited are infinitely varied, according to the nature of particular bodies.
If we take this quotation at face value, it is very difficult to see what possible set of physical circ.u.mstances could serve to falsify it. Just because it is so vague and indefinite (at least when taken out of context), it is unfalsifiable. Politicians and fortune-tellers can avoid being accused of making mistakes by making their a.s.sertions so vague that they can always be construed as compatible with whatever may eventuate. The demand for a high degree of falsifiability rules out such manoeuvres. The falsificationist demands that theories be stated with sufficient clarity to run the risk of falsification.
A similar situation exists with respect to precision. The more precisely a theory is formulated the more falsifiable it becomes. If we accept that the more falsifiable a theory is the better (provided it has not been falsified), then we must also accept that the more precise the claims of a theory are the better. "Planets move in ellipses around the sun" is more precise than "Planets move in closed loops around the sun", and is consequently more falsifiable. An oval orbit would falsify the first but not the second, whereas any orbit that falsifies the second will also falsify the first. The falsificationist is committed to preferring the first. Similarly, the falsificationist must prefer the claim that the velocity of light in a vacuum is 299.8 x 106 metres per second to the less-precise claim that it is about 300 x 106 metres per second, just because the first is more falsifiable than the second.
The closely a.s.sociated demands for precision and clarity of expression both follow naturally from the falsificationist's account of science.
Falsificationism and progress.
The progress of science as the falsificationist sees it might be summed up as follows. Science starts with problems, problems a.s.sociated with the explanation of the behaviour of some aspects of the world or universe. Falsifiable hypotheses are proposed by scientists as solutions to a problem. The conjectured hypotheses are then criticised and tested. Some will be quickly eliminated. Others might prove more successful. These must be subject to even more stringent criticism and_ testing. When an hypothesis that has successfully NVithstood a wide range of rigorous tests is eventually falsified, a new problem, hopefully far removed from the original solved problem, has emerged. This new problem calls for the invention of new hypotheses, followed by renewed criticism and testing. And so the process continues indefinitely. It can never be said of a theory that it is true, however well it has withstood rigorous tests, but it can hopefully be said that a current theory is superior to its predecessors in the sense that it is able to withstand tests that falsified those predecessors.
Before we look at some examples to ill.u.s.trate this falsificationist conception of the progress of science, a word should be said about the claim that "Science starts pith problems". Here are some problems that have confronted scientists in the past. How are bats able to fly so dexterously at night, when in fact they have very small, weak eyes? Why is the height of a simple barometer lower at high alt.i.tudes than at low alt.i.tudes? Why were the photographic plates in Roentgen's laboratory continually becoming blackened? Why does the perihelion of the planet Mercury advance? These problems arise from more or less straightforward observations. In insisting on the fact that science starts with problems, then, is it not the case that, for the falsificationist just as for the naive inductivist, science starts from observation? The answer to this question is a firm "No". The observations cited above as const.i.tuting problems are only problematic in the light of some theory. The first is problematic in the light of the theory that living organisms "see" with their eyes; the second was problematic for the supporters of Galileo's theories because it clashed with the "force of a vacuum" theory accepted by them as an explanation of why the mercury does not fall from a barometer tube; the third was problematic for Roentgen because it was tacitly a.s.sumed at the time that no radiation or emanation of any kind existed that could penetrate the container of the photographic plates and darken them; the fourth was problematic because it was incompatible with Newton's theory. The claim that science starts with problems is perfectly compatible with the priority of theories over observation and observation statements. Science does not start with stark observation.
After this digression, we return to the falsificationist conception of the progress of science as the progression from problems to speculative hypotheses, to their criticism and eventual falsification and thence to new problems. Two examples will be offered, the first a simple one concerning the flight of bats, the second a more ambitious one concerning the progress of physics.
We start with a problem. Bats are able to fly with ease and at speed, avoiding the branches of trees, telegraph wires other bats, etc., and can catch insects. And yet bats have weak eyes, and in any case do most of their flying at night. This poses a problem because it apparently falsifies the plausible theory that animals, like humans, see with their eyes. A falsificationist will attempt to solve the problem by making a conjecture or hypothesis. Perhaps he suggests that, although bats' eyes are apparently weak, nevertheless in some way that is not understood they are able to see efficiently at night by use of their eyes. This hypothesis can be tested. A sample of bats is released into a darkened room containing obstacles and their ability to avoid the obstacles measured in some way. The same bats are now blindfolded and again released into the room. Prior to the experiment, the experimenter can make the following deduction. One premise of the deduction is his hypothesis, which made quite explicit reads, "Bats are able to fly avoiding obstacles by using their eyes, and cannot do so without the use of their eyes". The second premise is a description of the experimental set-up, including the statement, "This sample of bats is blindfolded so that they do not have the use of their eyes". From these two premises, the experimenter can derive, deductively, that the sample of bats will not be able to avoid the obstacles in the test laboratory efficiently. The experiment is now performed and it is found that the bats avoid collisions just as efficiently as before. The hypothesis has been falsified. There is now a need for a fresh use of the imagination, a new conjecture or hypothesis or guess. Perhaps a scientist suggests that in some way the bat's 'ears are involved in its ability to avoid obstacles. The hypothesis can be tested, in an attempt to falsify it, by plugging the ears of bats before releasing them into the test laboratory. This time it is found that the ability of the bats to avoid obstacles is considerably impaired. The hypothesis has been supported. The falsificationist must now try to make the hypothesis more precise so that it becomes more readily falsifiable. It is suggested that the bat hears echoes of its own squeaks rebounding from solid objects. This is tested by gagging the bats before releasing them. Again the bats collide with obstacles and again the hypothesis is supported. The falsificationist now appears to be reaching a tentative solution to the problem, although it has not been proved by experiment how bats avoid collisions while flying. Any number of factors may turn up that show the hypothesis to have been wrong. Perhaps the bat detects echoes not with its ears but with sensitive regions close to the ears, the functioning of which was impaired when the bat's ears were plugged. Or perhaps different kinds of bats detect obstacles in very different ways, so the bats used in the experiment were not truly representative.
The progress of physics from Aristotle through Newton to Einstein provides an example on a larger scale. The falsificationist account of that progression goes something like this. Aristotelian physics was to some extent quite successful. It could explain a wide range of phenomena. It could explain why heavy objects fall to the ground (seeking their natural place at the centre of the universe), it could explain the action of siphons and liftpumps (the explanation being based on the impossibility of a Vacuum, and so on. But eventually Aristotelian physics was falsified in a number of ways. Stones dropped from the top of the mast of a uniformly moving s.h.i.+p fell to the deck at the foot of the mast and not some distance from the mast, as Aristotle's theory predicted. The moons of Jupiter can be seen to orbit Jupiter and not the earth. A host of other falsifications were acc.u.mulated during the seventeenth century. Newton's physics, however, once it had been created and developed by way of the conjectures of the likes of Galileo and Newton, was a superior theory that superseded Aristotle's. Newton's theory could account for falling objects, the operation of siphons and liftpumps and anything else that Aristotle's theory could explain, and could also account for the phenomena that were problematic for the Aristotelians. In addition, Newton's theory could explain phenomena not touched on by Aristotle's theory such as correlations between the tiles and the location of the moon, and the variation in the force of gravity with height above sea level. For two centuries Newton's theory was successful. That is, attempts to falsify it by reference to the new phenomena predicted with its help were unsuccessful. The theory even led to the discovery of a new planet, Neptune. But in spite of its success, sustained attempts to falsify it eventually proved successful. Newton's theory was falsified in a number of ways. It was unable to account for the details of the orbit of the planet Mercury and was unable to account for the variable ma.s.s of fast-moving electrons in discharge tubes. Challenging problems faced physicists, then, as the nineteenth century gave way to the twentieth, problems calling for new speculative hypotheses designed to overcome these problems in a progressive way. Einstein was able to meet this challenge. His relativity theory was able to account for the phenomena that falsified Newton's theory while at the same time being able to match Newton's theory in those areas where the latter had proved successful. In addition, Einstein's theory yielded the prediction of spectacular new phenomena. His special theory of relativity predicted that ma.s.s should be a function of velocity and that ma.s.s and energy could be transformed into one another, and his general theory predicted that light rays should be bent by strong gravitational fields. Attempts to refute Einstein's theory by reference to the new phenomena failed. The falsification of Einstein's theory remains a challenge for modern physicists. Their success, if it should eventuate, would mark a new step forward in the progress of physics.
So runs a typical falsification account of the progress of physics. Later we shall have cause to doubt its accuracy and validity.
From the foregoing, it is clear that the concept of progress, of the growth of science, is a conception that is a central one in the falsificationist account of science. This issue is pursued in more detail in the next chapter.
Further reading.
The cla.s.sic falsificationist text is Popper in The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1972), first published in German in 1934 and translated into English in 1959. More recent collections of his writings are Popper (1969) and Popper (1979). Popper's own story about how he came to his basic idea through comparing Freud, Adler and Marx with Einstein is in chapter 1 of his 1969 text. More sources related to falsificationism will be given at the end of the next chapter.
CHAPTER 6:.
Sophisticated falsificationism, novel predictions and the growth of science.
Relative rather than absolute degrees of falsifiability.
The previous chapter mentioned some conditions that an hypothesis should satisfy in order to be worthy of a scientist's consideration. An hypothesis should be falsifiable, the more falsifiable the better, and yet should not be falsified. More sophisticated falsificationists realise that those conditions alone are insufficient. A further condition is connected with the need for science to progress. An hypothesis should be more falsifiable than the one for which it is offered as a replacement.
The sophisticated falsificationist account of science, with its emphasis on the growth of science, switches the focus of attention from the merits of a single theory to the relative merits of competing theories. It gives a dynamic picture of science rather than the static account of the most naive falsificationists. Instead of asking of a theory "Is it falsifiable?", "How falsifiable is it?" and "Has it been falsified?", it becomes more appropriate to ask, "Is this newly proposed theory a viable replacement for the one it challenges?" In general, a newly proposed theory will be acceptable as worthy of the consideration of scientists if it is more falsifiable than its rival, and especially if it predicts a new kind of phenomenon not touched on by its rival.
The emphasis on the comparison of degrees of falsifiability of series of theories, which is a consequence of the emphasis on a science as a growing and evolving body of knowledge, enables a technical problem to be bypa.s.sed. For it is very difficult to specify just how falsifiable a single theory is. An absolute measure of falsifiability cannot be defined simply because the number of potential falsifiers of a theory will always be infinite. It is difficult to see how the question "How falsifiable is Newton's law of gravitation?" could be answered. On the other hand, it is often possible to compare the degrees of falsifiability of laws or theories. For instance, the claim "All pairs of bodies attract each other with a force that varies inversely as the square of their separation" is more falsifiable than the claim "The planets in the solar system attract each other with a force that varies inversely as the square of their separation". The second is implied by the first. Anything that falsifies the second will falsify the first, but the reverse is not true. Ideally, the falsificationist would like to be able to say that the series of theories that const.i.tute the historical evolution of a science is made up of falsifiable theories, each one in the series being more falsifiable than its predecessor.
Increasing falsifiability and ad hoc modifications.
The demand that as a science progresses its theories should become more and more faisifiable, and consequently have more and more content and be more and more informative, rules out modifications in theories that are designed merely to protect a theory from a threatening falsification.A modification in a theory, such as the addition of an extra postulate or a change in some existing postulate, that ,has n7) testable consequences that were not already testable consequences of the unmodified theory will be called ad hoc modifications. The remainder of this section will consist of examples designed to clarify the notion of an ad hoc modification. I will first consider some ad hoc modifications, which the falsificationist would reject, and afterwards these will be contrasted with some modifications that are not ad hoc and which the falsificationist would consequently welcome.
I begin with a rather trivial example. Let us consider the generalisation "Bread nourishes". This low-level theory, if spelt out in more detail, amounts to the claim that if wieat is grown in the not way, converted into bread in the normal way and eaten by humans in a normal way, then those humans will be nourished. This apparently innocuous theory ran into trouble in a French village on an occasion when wheat was grown in a normal way, converted into bread in a normal way and yet most people who ate the bread became seriously ill and many died. The theory "(All) bread nourishes" was falsified. The theory can be modified to avoid this falsification by adjusting it to read, "(All) bread, with the exception of that particular batch of bread produced in the French village in question, nourishes". This is an ad hoc modification. The modified theory cannot be tested in any way that was not also a test of the original theory. The consuming of any bread by any human const.i.tutes a test of the original theory, whereas tests of the modified theory are restricted to the consuming of bread other than that batch of bread that led to such disastrous results in France. The modified hypothesis is less falsifiable than the original version. The falsificationist rejects such rearguard actions.
The next example is less gruesome and more entertaining. It is an example based on an interchange that actually took place in the seventeenth century between Galileo and an Aristotelian adversary. Having carefully observed the moon through his newly invented telescope, Galileo was able to report that the moon was not a smooth sphere but that its surface abounded in mountains and craters. His Aristotelian adversary had to admit that things did appear that way when he repeated the observations for himself. But the observations threatened a notion fundamental for many Aristotelians, namely that all celestial bodies are perfect spheres. Galileo's rival defended his theory in the face of the apparent falsification in a way that was blatantly ad hoc. He suggested that there was an invisible substance on the moon filling the craters and covering the mountains in such a way that the moon's shape was perfectly spherical. When Galileo inquired how the presence of the invisible substance might be detected, the reply was that there was no way in which it could be detected. There is no doubt, then, that the modified theory led to no new testable consequences and would be quite unacceptable to a falsificationist. An exasperated Galileo was able to show up the inadequacy of his rival's position in a characteristically Witty way. He announced that he was prepared to admit that the invisible, undetectable substance existed on the moon, but insisted that it was not distributed in the way suggested by his rival but in fact was piled up on top of the mountains so that they were many times higher than they appeared through the telescope. Galileo was able to outmanoeuvre n the fruitless game of the invention of ad hoc devices for the protection of theories.
One other example of a possibly ad hoc hypothesis from the history of science will be briefly mentioned. Prior to Lavoisier, the phlogiston theory was the standard theory of combustion. According to that theory, phlogiston is emitted from substances when they are burnt. This theory was thiaTeried when it was discovered that many substances gain weight after combustion. One way of overcoming the apparent falsification was to suggest that phlogiston has negative weight. If this hypothesis could be tested only by weighing substances before and after combustion, then it was ad hoc. It led to no new tests.
Modifications of a theory in an attempt to overcome a difficulty need not be ad hoc. Here are some examples of modifications that are not ad hoc, and which consequently are acceptable from a falsificationist point of view.
Let us return to the falsification of the claim "Bread nourishes" to see how this could be modified in an acceptable way. An acceptable move would be to replace the original falsified theory by the claim "All bread nourishes except bread made from wheat contaminated by a particular kind of fungus" (followed by a specification of the fungus and some of its characteristics). This modified theory is not ad hoc because it leads to new tests. It is independently testable, to use Popper's (1972, p. 193) phrase. Possible tests would include testing the wheat from which the poisonous bread was made for the presence of the fungus, cultivating the fungus on some specially prepared wheat and testing the nouris.h.i.+ng effect of the bread produced from it, chemically a.n.a.lysing the fungus for the presence of known poisons, and so on. All these tests, many of which do not const.i.tute tests of the original hypothesis, could result in the falsification of the modified hypothesis. If the modified more falsifiable, hypothesis resists falsification iathe face of the new tests, then something new will have been learnt and progress will have been made.
Turning now to the history of science for a less artificial example, we might consider the train of events that led to the discovery of the planet Neptune. Nineteenth-century observations of the motion of the planet Ura.n.u.s indicated that its...o...b..t deriartefi considerably from that predicted on the basis of Newton's gravitational theory, thus posing a problem for that theory. In an attempt to overcome the difficulty, it was suggested by Leverrier in France and by Adams in England that there existed a previously undetected planet in the vicinity of Ura.n.u.s. The attraction between the conjectured planet and Ura.n.u.s was to account for the latter's departure from its initially predicted orbit. This suggestion was not ad hoc, as events were to show. It was possible to estimate the approximate vicinity of the conjectural planet if it were to be of a reasonable size and to be responsible for the perturbation of Ura.n.u.s' orbit. Once this had been done, it was possible to test the new proposal by inspecting the appropriate region of the sky through a telescope. It was in this way that Galle came to make the first sighting of the planet now known as Neptune. Far from being ad hoc, the move to save Newton's theory from falsification by Ura.n.u.s's...o...b..t led to a new kind of test of that theory, which it was able to pa.s.s in a dramatic and progressive way.
Confirmation in the falsificationist account of science.
When falsificationism was introduced as an alternative to inductivism in the previous chapter, falsifications (that is, the failures of theories to stand up to observational and experimental tests) were portrayed as being of key importance. It was argued that the logical situation permits the establishment of the falsity but not of the truth of theories in the light of available observation statements. It was also ' urged that science should progress by the proposal of bold, highly falsifiable conjectures as attempts to solve problems, followed by ruthless attempts to falsify the new proposals. Along with this came the suggestion that significant advances in science come about when those bold conjectures are falsified. The self-avowed falsificationist Popper says a''s in the pa.s.sage quoted on pp. 66-7, where the italics are his. However, exclusive attention to falsifying instances amounts to a misrepresentation of the more sophisticated falsificationist's position. More than a hint of this is contained in the example with which the previous section concluded. The independently testable attempt to save Newton's theory by a speculative hypothesis was a success because that hypothesis was confirmed by the discovery of Neptune and not because it was falsified.
It is a mistake to regard the falsification of bold, highly falsifiable conjectures as the occasions of significant advance in science, and Popper needs to be corrected on this point. This becomes clear when we consider the various extreme possibilities. At one extreme we have theories that take the form of bold, risky conjectures, while at the other we have theories that are cautious conjectures, making claims that seem to involve no significant risks. If either kind of conjecture fails an observational or experimental test it will be falsified, and if it pa.s.ses such a test we will say it is confirmed. Significant advances will be marked by the confirmation of bold conjectures or the falsification of cautious conjectures. Cases of the former kind will be informative, and const.i.tute an important contribution to scientific knowledge, simply because they mark the discovery of something that was previously unheard of or considered unlikely. The discovery of Neptune and of radio waves and Eddington's confirmation of Einstein's risky prediction that light rays should bend in strong gravitational fields all const.i.tuted significant advances of this kind. Risky predictions were confirmed. The falsification of cautious conjectures is informative because it establishes that what was regarded as problematically true is in fact false. Russell's demonstration that naive set theory, which was based on what appear to be almost self-evident propositions, is inconsistent is an example of an informative falsification of a conjecture apparently free from risk. Itycontrast, little is learnt from the falsification of a bold conjecture or the confirmation of a cautious conjecture. If a bold conjecture is falsified, then all that is learnt is that yet another crazy idea has been proved wrong. The falsification of Kepler's speculation that the s.p.a.cing of the planetary orbits could be explained by reference to Plato's five regular solids does not mark one of the significant landmarks in the progress of physics. Similarly, the confirmation of cautious hypotheses is uninformative. Such confirmations merely indicate that some theory that was well established and regarded as unproblematic has been successfully applied once again. For instance, the confirmation of the conjecture that samples of iron extracted from itsfiiby some new process will, like other iron, expand when heated would be of little consequence.
The falsificationist wishes to reject ad hoc hypotheses and to encourage the proposal of bold hypotheses as potential improvements on falsified theories. Those bold hypotheses will lead to novel, testable predictions, which do not follow from the original, falsified theory. However, although the fact that it does ,lead to the possibility of new tests makes an hypothesis worthy of investigation, it will not rank as an improvement on the problematic theory it is designed to replace until it has survived at least some of those tests. This is t.i.taiiiant to saying that before it can be regarded as an adequate replacement for a falsified theory, a newly and boldly proposed theory must make some novel predictions that are confirmed. Many wild and rash speculations will not survive subsequent testing and consequently will not be rated as contributing to the growth of scientific knowledge. The occasional wild and rash speculation that does lead to a novel, unlikely prediction, which is nevertheless confirmed by observation or experiment, will thereby become established as highlight in the history of the growth of science. The confirmations of novel predictions resulting from bold conjectures are very important in the falsificationist account of the growth of science.
Boldness, novelty and background knowledge.
A little more needs to be said about the adjectives "bold" and "novel" as applied to hypotheses and predictions respectively. They are both historically relative notions. What rates as a bold conjecture at one stage in the history of science may no longer be bold at some later stage. When Maxwell proposed his "dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field" in 1864, it was a bold conjecture. It was bold because it conflicted with theories generally accepted at the time, theories that included the a.s.sumption that electromagnetic systems (magnets, charged bodies, current-carrying conductors) act upon each other instantaneously across empty s.p.a.ce and that electromagnetic effects can be propagated at a finite velocity only through material substances. Maxwell's theory clashed with these generally accepted a.s.sumptions because it predicted that light is an electromagnetic phenomenon and also predicted, as was to be realised later, that fluctuating currents should emit a new kind of radiation, radio waves, travelling at a finite velocity through empty s.p.a.ce. In 1864, therefore, Maxwell's theory was bold and the subsequent prediction of radio waves was a novel prediction. Today, the fact that Maxwell's theory can give an accurate account of the behaviour of a wide range of electromagnetic systems is a generally accepted part of scientific knowledge, and a.s.sertions about the existence and properties of radio waves will not rate as novel predictions.
If we call the complex of scientific theories generally accepted and well established at some stage in the history of science the background knowledge of the time, then we can say that a conjecture will be bold if its claims are the light of the background knowledge of the time. Einstein's general theory of relativity was a bold one in 1915 because at that time background knowledge included, the a.s.sumption that light travels in straight lines. This clashed with one consequence of general relativity, namely that light rays should bend in strong gravitational fields. Copernicus's astronomy was bold in 1543 because it clashed with the background a.s.sumption that the earth is stationary at the centre of the universe. It would not be considered bold today.
Just as conjectures will be considered bold or otherwise by reference to the relevant background knowledge, so predictions will bejudged novel if they involve some phenomenon that does not figure in, or is perhaps explicitly ruled out by, the background knowledge of the time. The prediction of Neptune in 1846 was a novel one because the background knowledge at that time contained no reference to such a planet. The prediction that Poisson deduced from Fresnel's wave theory of light in 1818, namely that a bright spot should be observed at the centre of one side of an opaque disc suitably illuminated from the other, was novel because the existence of that bright spot was ruled out by the particle theory of light that formed part of the background knowledge of the time.
In the previous section it was argued that major contributions to the growth of scientific knowledge come about either when a bold conjecture is confirmed or when a cautious conjecture is falsified. The idea of background knowledge enables us to see that these two possibilities will occur together as the result of a single experiment. Background knowledge consists of cautious hypotheses just because that, knowledge is well established and considered to be unproblematic. The confirmation of a bold conjecture will involve the falsification of some part of the background knowledge with respect to which the conjecture was bold.
Comparison of the inductivist and falsificationist view of confirmation.
We have seen that confirmation has an important role to play in science as interpreted by the sophisticated falsificationist. However, this does not totally invalidate the labelling of that position "falsificationism". It is still maintained by the sophisticated falsificationist that theories can be falsified and rejected, while it is denied that theories can ever be established as true or probably true. The aim of science is to falsify theories and to replace them by better theories, theories that demonstrate a greater ability to withstand tests. Confirmations of new theories are important insofar as they const.i.tute evidence that a new theory is an improvement on the theory it replaces, the theory that is falsified by the evidence unearthed with the aid of, and confirming, the new theory Once a newly proposed bold theory has succeeded in ousting its rival, then it in turn becomes a new target at which stringent tests should be directed, tests devised with the aid of further boldly conjectured theories.
Because of the falsificationists' emphasis on the growth of science, their account of confirmation is significantly different from that of the inductivists. The significance of some confirming instances of a theory according to the extreme inductivist position described in chapter 4 is determined solely by the logical relations.h.i.+p between the observation statements that are confirmed and the theory that they support. The degree of support given to Newton's theory by Galle's observation of Neptune is no different from the degree of support given by a modern observation of Neptune. The historical context in. which the evidence is acquired is irrelevant. Confirming instances are such if they give inductive support to a theory, and the greater the number of confirming instances established, the greater the support for the theory and the more likely it is to be true. This ahistorical theory of confirmation would seem to have the unappealing consequence that innumerable observations made on falling stones, planetary positions, etc. will const.i.tute worthwhile scientific activity insofar as they will lead to increases in the estimate of the probability of the truth of the law of gravitation.
By contrast, in the falsificationist account, the significance of confirmations depends very much on their historical context. A confirmation will confer some high degree of merit on a theory if that confirmation resulted from the testing of a novel prediction. That is, a confirmation will be significant if it is estimated that it is unlikely to eventuate in the light of the background knowledge of the time. Confirmations that are foregone conclusions are insignificant. If today I confirm Newton's theory by dropping a stone to the ground, I contribute nothing of value to science. On the other hand, if tomorrow I confirm a speculative theory implying that the gravitational attraction between two bodies depends on their temperature, falsifying Newton's theory in the process, I would have made a significant contribution to scientific knowledge. Newton's theory of gravitation and some of its limitations are part of current background knowledge, whereas a temperature dependence of gravitational attraction is not. Here is one further example in support of the historical perspective that the falsificationists introduce into confirmation. Hertz confirmed Maxwell's theory when he detected the first radio waves. I also confirm Maxwell's theory whenever I listen to my radio. The logical situation is similar in the two cases. In each case, the theory predicts that radio waves should be detected and, M each case, their successful detection lends some inductive support to the theory. Nevertheless, Hertz is justly famous for the confirmation he achieved, whereas my frequent confirmations are rightly ignored in a scientific context. Hertz made a significant step forward. When I listen to my radio I am only marking time. The historical context makes all the difference.