The philosophy of mathematics - LightNovelsOnl.com
You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.
_Advantages of introducing Trigonometrical Lines._ At the present day, since the solution can be obtained by either system indifferently, that motive for preference no longer exists; but geometers have none the less persisted in following from choice the system primitively admitted from necessity; for, the same reason which enabled these trigonometrical equations to be obtained with much more facility, must, in like manner, as it is still more easy to conceive _a priori_, render these equations much more simple, since they then exist only between right lines, instead of being established between right lines and arcs of circles.
Such a consideration has so much the more importance, as the question relates to formulas which are eminently elementary, and destined to be continually employed in all parts of mathematical science, as well as in all its various applications.
It may be objected, however, that when an angle is given, it is, in reality, always given by itself, and not by its trigonometrical lines; and that when it is unknown, it is its angular value which is properly to be determined, and not that of any of its trigonometrical lines. It seems, according to this, that such lines are only useless intermediaries between the sides and the angles, which have to be finally eliminated, and the introduction of which does not appear capable of simplifying the proposed research. It is indeed important to explain, with more generality and precision than is customary, the great real utility of this manner of proceeding.
_Division of Trigonometry into two Parts._ It consists in the fact that the introduction of these auxiliary magnitudes divides the entire question of trigonometry into two others essentially distinct, one of which has for its object to pa.s.s from the angles to their trigonometrical lines, or the converse, and the other of which proposes to determine the sides of the triangles by the trigonometrical lines of their angles, or the converse. Now the first of these two fundamental questions is evidently susceptible, by its nature, of being entirely treated and reduced to numerical tables once for all, in considering all possible angles, since it depends only upon those angles, and not at all upon the particular triangles in which they may enter in each case; while the solution of the second question must necessarily be renewed, at least in its arithmetical relations, for each new triangle which it is necessary to resolve. This is the reason why the first portion of the complete work, which would be precisely the most laborious, is no longer taken into the account, being always done in advance; while, if such a decomposition had not been performed, we would evidently have found ourselves under the obligation of recommencing the entire calculation in each particular case. Such is the essential property of the present trigonometrical system, which in fact would really present no actual advantage, if it was necessary to calculate continually the trigonometrical line of each angle to be considered, or the converse; the intermediate agency introduced would then be more troublesome than convenient.
In order to clearly comprehend the true nature of this conception, it will be useful to compare it with a still more important one, designed to produce an a.n.a.logous effect either in its algebraic, or, still more, in its arithmetical relations--the admirable theory of _logarithms_. In examining in a philosophical manner the influence of this theory, we see in fact that its general result is to decompose all imaginable arithmetical operations into two distinct parts. The first and most complicated of these is capable of being executed in advance once for all (since it depends only upon the numbers to be considered, and not at all upon the infinitely different combinations into which they can enter), and consists in considering all numbers as a.s.signable powers of a constant number. The second part of the calculation, which must of necessity be recommenced for each new formula which is to have its value determined, is thenceforth reduced to executing upon these exponents correlative operations which are infinitely more simple. I confine myself here to merely indicating this resemblance, which any one can carry out for himself.
We must besides observe, as a property (secondary at the present day, but all-important at its origin) of the trigonometrical system adopted, the very remarkable circ.u.mstance that the determination of angles by their trigonometrical lines, or the converse, admits of an arithmetical solution (the only one which is directly indispensable for the special destination of trigonometry) without the previous resolution of the corresponding algebraic question. It is doubtless to such a peculiarity that the ancients owed the possibility of knowing trigonometry. The investigation conceived in this way was so much the more easy, inasmuch as tables of chords (which the ancients naturally took as the trigonometrical lines) had been previously constructed for quite a different object, in the course of the labours of Archimedes on the rectification of the circle, from which resulted the actual determination of a certain series of chords; so that when Hipparchus subsequently invented trigonometry, he could confine himself to completing that operation by suitable intercalations; which shows clearly the connexion of ideas in that matter.
_The Increase of such Trigonometrical Lines._ To complete this philosophical sketch of trigonometry, it is proper now to observe that the extension of the same considerations which lead us to replace angles or arcs of circles by straight lines, with the view of simplifying our equations, must also lead us to employ concurrently several trigonometrical lines, instead of confining ourselves to one only (as did the ancients), so as to perfect this system by choosing that one which will be algebraically the most convenient on each occasion. In this point of view, it is clear that the number of these lines is in itself no ways limited; provided that they are determined by the arc, and that they determine it, whatever may be the law according to which they are derived from it, they are suitable to be subst.i.tuted for it in the equations. The Arabians, and subsequently the moderns, in confining themselves to the most simple constructions, have carried to four or five the number of _direct_ trigonometrical lines, which might be extended much farther.
But instead of recurring to geometrical formations, which would finally become very complicated, we conceive with the utmost facility as many new trigonometrical lines as the a.n.a.lytical transformations may require, by means of a remarkable artifice, which is not usually apprehended in a sufficiently general manner. It consists in not directly multiplying the trigonometrical lines appropriate to each arc considered, but in introducing new ones, by considering this arc as indirectly determined by all lines relating to an arc which is a very simple function of the first. It is thus, for example, that, in order to calculate an angle with more facility, we will determine, instead of its sine, the sine of its half, or of its double, &c. Such a creation of _indirect_ trigonometrical lines is evidently much more fruitful than all the direct geometrical methods for obtaining new ones. We may accordingly say that the number of trigonometrical lines actually employed at the present day by geometers is in reality unlimited, since at every instant, so to say, the transformations of a.n.a.lysis may lead us to augment it by the method which I have just indicated. Special names, however, have been given to those only of these _indirect_ lines which refer to the complement of the primitive arc, the others not occurring sufficiently often to render such denominations necessary; a circ.u.mstance which has caused a common misconception of the true extent of the system of trigonometry.
_Study of their Mutual Relations._ This multiplicity of trigonometrical lines evidently gives rise to a third fundamental question in trigonometry, the study of the relations which exist between these different lines; since, without such a knowledge, we could not make use, for our a.n.a.lytical necessities, of this variety of auxiliary magnitudes, which, however, have no other destination. It is clear, besides, from the consideration just indicated, that this essential part of trigonometry, although simply preparatory, is, by its nature, susceptible of an indefinite extension when we view it in its entire generality, while the two others are circ.u.mscribed within rigorously defined limits.
It is needless to add that these three princ.i.p.al parts of trigonometry have to be studied in precisely the inverse order from that in which we have seen them necessarily derived from the general nature of the subject; for the third is evidently independent of the two others, and the second, of that which was first presented--the resolution of triangles, properly so called--which must for that reason be treated in the last place; which rendered so much the more important the consideration of their natural succession and logical relations to one another.
It is useless to consider here separately _spherical trigonometry_, which cannot give rise to any special philosophical consideration; since, essential as it is by the importance and the multiplicity of its uses, it can be treated at the present day only as a simple application of rectilinear trigonometry, which furnishes directly its fundamental equations, by subst.i.tuting for the spherical triangle the corresponding trihedral angle.
This summary exposition of the philosophy of trigonometry has been here given in order to render apparent, by an important example, that rigorous dependence and those successive ramifications which are presented by what are apparently the most simple questions of elementary geometry.
Having thus examined the peculiar character of _special_ geometry reduced to its only dogmatic destination, that of furnis.h.i.+ng to general geometry an indispensable preliminary basis, we have now to give all our attention to the true science of geometry, considered as a whole, in the most rational manner. For that purpose, it is necessary to carefully examine the great original idea of Descartes, upon which it is entirely founded. This will be the object of the following chapter.
CHAPTER III.
MODERN OR a.n.a.lYTICAL GEOMETRY.
_General_ (or _a.n.a.lytical_) geometry being entirely founded upon the transformation of geometrical considerations into equivalent a.n.a.lytical considerations, we must begin with examining directly and in a thorough manner the beautiful conception by which Descartes has established in a uniform manner the constant possibility of such a co-relation. Besides its own extreme importance as a means of highly perfecting geometrical science, or, rather, of establis.h.i.+ng the whole of it on rational bases, the philosophical study of this admirable conception must have so much the greater interest in our eyes from its characterizing with perfect clearness the general method to be employed in organizing the relations of the abstract to the concrete in mathematics, by the a.n.a.lytical representation of natural phenomena. There is no conception, in the whole philosophy of mathematics which better deserves to fix all our attention.
a.n.a.lYTICAL REPRESENTATION OF FIGURES.
In order to succeed in expressing all imaginable geometrical phenomena by simple a.n.a.lytical relations, we must evidently, in the first place, establish a general method for representing a.n.a.lytically the subjects themselves in which these phenomena are found, that is, the lines or the surfaces to be considered. The _subject_ being thus habitually considered in a purely a.n.a.lytical point of view, we see how it is thenceforth possible to conceive in the same manner the various _accidents_ of which it is susceptible.
In order to organize the representation of geometrical figures by a.n.a.lytical equations, we must previously surmount a fundamental difficulty; that of reducing the general elements of the various conceptions of geometry to simply numerical ideas; in a word, that of subst.i.tuting in geometry pure considerations of _quant.i.ty_ for all considerations of _quality_.
_Reduction of Figure to Position._ For this purpose let us observe, in the first place, that all geometrical ideas relate necessarily to these three universal categories: the _magnitude_, the _figure_, and the _position_ of the extensions to be considered. As to the first, there is evidently no difficulty; it enters at once into the ideas of numbers.
With relation to the second, it must be remarked that it will always admit of being reduced to the third. For the figure of a body evidently results from the mutual position of the different points of which it is composed, so that the idea of position necessarily comprehends that of figure, and every circ.u.mstance of figure can be translated by a circ.u.mstance of position. It is in this way, in fact, that the human mind has proceeded in order to arrive at the a.n.a.lytical representation of geometrical figures, their conception relating directly only to positions. All the elementary difficulty is then properly reduced to that of referring ideas of situation to ideas of magnitude. Such is the direct destination of the preliminary conception upon which Descartes has established the general system of a.n.a.lytical geometry.
His philosophical labour, in this relation, has consisted simply in the entire generalization of an elementary operation, which we may regard as natural to the human mind, since it is performed spontaneously, so to say, in all minds, even the most uncultivated. Thus, when we have to indicate the situation of an object without directly pointing it out, the method which we always adopt, and evidently the only one which can be employed, consists in referring that object to others which are known, by a.s.signing the magnitude of the various geometrical elements, by which we conceive it connected with the known objects. These elements const.i.tute what Descartes, and after him all geometers, have called the _co-ordinates_ of each point considered. They are necessarily two in number, if it is known in advance in what plane the point is situated; and three, if it may be found indifferently in any region of s.p.a.ce. As many different constructions as can be imagined for determining the position of a point, whether on a plane or in s.p.a.ce, so many distinct systems of co-ordinates may be conceived; they are consequently susceptible of being multiplied to infinity. But, whatever may be the system adopted, we shall always have reduced the ideas of situation to simple ideas of magnitude, so that we will consider the change in the position of a point as produced by mere numerical variations in the values of its co-ordinates.
_Determination of the Position of a Point._ Considering at first only the least complicated case, that of _plane geometry_, it is in this way that we usually determine the position of a point on a plane, by its distances from two fixed right lines considered as known, which are called _axes_, and which are commonly supposed to be perpendicular to each other. This system is that most frequently adopted, because of its simplicity; but geometers employ occasionally an infinity of others.
Thus the position of a point on a plane may be determined, 1, by its distances from two fixed points; or, 2, by its distance from a single fixed point, and the direction of that distance, estimated by the greater or less angle which it makes with a fixed right line, which const.i.tutes the system of what are called _polar_ co-ordinates, the most frequently used after the system first mentioned; or, 3, by the angles which the right lines drawn from the variable point to two fixed points make with the right line which joins these last; or, 4, by the distances from that point to a fixed right line and a fixed point, &c.
In a word, there is no geometrical figure whatever from which it is not possible to deduce a certain system of co-ordinates more or less susceptible of being employed.
A general observation, which it is important to make in this connexion, is, that every system of co-ordinates is equivalent to determining a point, in plane geometry, by the intersection of two lines, each of which is subjected to certain fixed conditions of determination; a single one of these conditions remaining variable, sometimes the one, sometimes the other, according to the system considered. We could not, indeed, conceive any other means of constructing a point than to mark it by the meeting of two lines. Thus, in the most common system, that of _rectilinear co-ordinates_, properly so called, the point is determined by the intersection of two right lines, each of which remains constantly parallel to a fixed axis, at a greater or less distance from it; in the _polar_ system, the position of the point is marked by the meeting of a circle, of variable radius and fixed centre, with a movable right line compelled to turn about this centre: in other systems, the required point might be designated by the intersection of two circles, or of any other two lines, &c. In a word, to a.s.sign the value of one of the co-ordinates of a point in any system whatever, is always necessarily equivalent to determining a certain line on which that point must be situated. The geometers of antiquity had already made this essential remark, which served as the base of their method of geometrical _loci_, of which they made so happy a use to direct their researches in the resolution of _determinate_ problems, in considering separately the influence of each of the two conditions by which was defined each point const.i.tuting the object, direct or indirect, of the proposed question.
It was the general systematization of this method which was the immediate motive of the labours of Descartes, which led him to create a.n.a.lytical geometry.
After having clearly established this preliminary conception--by means of which ideas of position, and thence, implicitly, all elementary geometrical conceptions are capable of being reduced to simple numerical considerations--it is easy to form a direct conception, in its entire generality, of the great original idea of Descartes, relative to the a.n.a.lytical representation of geometrical figures: it is this which forms the special object of this chapter. I will continue to consider at first, for more facility, only geometry of two dimensions, which alone was treated by Descartes; and will afterwards examine separately, under the same point of view, the theory of surfaces and curves of double curvature.
PLANE CURVES.
_Expression of Lines by Equations._ In accordance with the manner of expressing a.n.a.lytically the position of a point on a plane, it can be easily established that, by whatever property any line may be defined, that definition always admits of being replaced by a corresponding equation between the two variable co-ordinates of the point which describes this line; an equation which will be thenceforth the a.n.a.lytical representation of the proposed line, every phenomenon of which will be translated by a certain algebraic modification of its equation. Thus, if we suppose that a point moves on a plane without its course being in any manner determined, we shall evidently have to regard its co-ordinates, to whatever system they may belong, as two variables entirely independent of one another. But if, on the contrary, this point is compelled to describe a certain line, we shall necessarily be compelled to conceive that its co-ordinates, in all the positions which it can take, retain a certain permanent and precise relation to each other, which is consequently susceptible of being expressed by a suitable equation; which will become the very clear and very rigorous a.n.a.lytical definition of the line under consideration, since it will express an algebraical property belonging exclusively to the co-ordinates of all the points of this line. It is clear, indeed, that when a point is not subjected to any condition, its situation is not determined except in giving at once its two co-ordinates, independently of each other; while, when the point must continue upon a defined line, a single co-ordinate is sufficient for completely fixing its position.
The second co-ordinate is then a determinate _function_ of the first; or, in other words, there must exist between them a certain _equation_, of a nature corresponding to that of the line on which the point is compelled to remain. In a word, each of the co-ordinates of a point requiring it to be situated on a certain line, we conceive reciprocally that the condition, on the part of a point, of having to belong to a line defined in any manner whatever, is equivalent to a.s.signing the value of one of the two co-ordinates; which is found in that case to be entirely dependent on the other. The a.n.a.lytical relation which expresses this dependence may be more or less difficult to discover, but it must evidently be always conceived to exist, even in the cases in which our present means may be insufficient to make it known. It is by this simple consideration that we may demonstrate, in an entirely general manner--independently of the particular verifications on which this fundamental conception is ordinarily established for each special definition of a line--the necessity of the a.n.a.lytical representation of lines by equations.
_Expression of Equations by Lines._ Taking up again the same reflections in the inverse direction, we could show as easily the geometrical necessity of the representation of every equation of two variables, in a determinate system of co-ordinates, by a certain line; of which such a relation would be, in the absence of any other known property, a very characteristic definition, the scientific destination of which will be to fix the attention directly upon the general course of the solutions of the equation, which will thus be noted in the most striking and the most simple manner. This picturing of equations is one of the most important fundamental advantages of a.n.a.lytical geometry, which has thereby reacted in the highest degree upon the general perfecting of a.n.a.lysis itself; not only by a.s.signing to purely abstract researches a clearly determined object and an inexhaustible career, but, in a still more direct relation, by furnis.h.i.+ng a new philosophical medium for a.n.a.lytical meditation which could not be replaced by any other. In fact, the purely algebraic discussion of an equation undoubtedly makes known its solutions in the most precise manner, but in considering them only one by one, so that in this way no general view of them could be obtained, except as the final result of a long and laborious series of numerical comparisons. On the other hand, the geometrical _locus_ of the equation, being only designed to represent distinctly and with perfect clearness the summing up of all these comparisons, permits it to be directly considered, without paying any attention to the details which have furnished it. It can thereby suggest to our mind general a.n.a.lytical views, which we should have arrived at with much difficulty in any other manner, for want of a means of clearly characterizing their object. It is evident, for example, that the simple inspection of the logarithmic curve, or of the curve _y_ = sin. _x_, makes us perceive much more distinctly the general manner of the variations of logarithms with respect to their numbers, or of sines with respect to their arcs, than could the most attentive study of a table of logarithms or of natural sines. It is well known that this method has become entirely elementary at the present day, and that it is employed whenever it is desired to get a clear idea of the general character of the law which reigns in a series of precise observations of any kind whatever.
_Any Change in the Line causes a Change in the Equation._ Returning to the representation of lines by equations, which is our princ.i.p.al object, we see that this representation is, by its nature, so faithful, that the line could not experience any modification, however slight it might be, without causing a corresponding change in the equation. This perfect exact.i.tude even gives rise oftentimes to special difficulties; for since, in our system of a.n.a.lytical geometry, the mere displacements of lines affect the equations, as well as their real variations in magnitude or form, we should be liable to confound them with one another in our a.n.a.lytical expressions, if geometers had not discovered an ingenious method designed expressly to always distinguish them. This method is founded on this principle, that although it is impossible to change a.n.a.lytically at will the position of a line with respect to the axes of the co-ordinates, we can change in any manner whatever the situation of the axes themselves, which evidently amounts to the same; then, by the aid of the very simple general formula by which this transformation of the axes is produced, it becomes easy to discover whether two different equations are the a.n.a.lytical expressions of only the same line differently situated, or refer to truly distinct geometrical loci; since, in the former case, one of them will pa.s.s into the other by suitably changing the axes or the other constants of the system of co-ordinates employed. It must, moreover, be remarked on this subject, that general inconveniences of this nature seem to be absolutely inevitable in a.n.a.lytical geometry; for, since the ideas of position are, as we have seen, the only geometrical ideas immediately reducible to numerical considerations, and the conceptions of figure cannot be thus reduced, except by seeing in them relations of situation, it is impossible for a.n.a.lysis to escape confounding, at first, the phenomena of figure with simple phenomena of position, which alone are directly expressed by the equations.
_Every Definition of a Line is an Equation._ In order to complete the philosophical explanation of the fundamental conception which serves as the base of a.n.a.lytical geometry, I think that I should here indicate a new general consideration, which seems to me particularly well adapted for putting in the clearest point of view this necessary representation of lines by equations with two variables. It consists in this, that not only, as we have shown, must every defined line necessarily give rise to a certain equation between the two co-ordinates of any one of its points, but, still farther, every definition of a line may be regarded as being already of itself an equation of that line in a suitable system of co-ordinates.
It is easy to establish this principle, first making a preliminary logical distinction with respect to different kinds of definitions. The rigorously indispensable condition of every definition is that of distinguis.h.i.+ng the object defined from all others, by a.s.signing to it a property which belongs to it exclusively. But this end may be generally attained in two very different ways; either by a definition which is simply _characteristic_, that is, indicative of a property which, although truly exclusive, does not make known the mode of generation of the object; or by a definition which is really _explanatory_, that is, which characterizes the object by a property which expresses one of its modes of generation. For example, in considering the circle as the line, which, under the same contour, contains the greatest area, we have evidently a definition of the first kind; while in choosing the property of its having all its points equally distant from a fixed point, we have a definition of the second kind. It is, besides, evident, as a general principle, that even when any object whatever is known at first only by a _characteristic_ definition, we ought, nevertheless, to regard it as susceptible of _explanatory_ definitions, which the farther study of the object would necessarily lead us to discover.
This being premised, it is clear that the general observation above made, which represents every definition of a line as being necessarily an equation of that line in a certain system of co-ordinates, cannot apply to definitions which are simply _characteristic_; it is to be understood only of definitions which are truly _explanatory_. But, in considering only this cla.s.s, the principle is easy to prove. In fact, it is evidently impossible to define the generation of a line without specifying a certain relation between the two simple motions of translation or of rotation, into which the motion of the point which describes it will be decomposed at each instant. Now if we form the most general conception of what const.i.tutes _a system of co-ordinates_, and admit all possible systems, it is clear that such a relation will be nothing else but the _equation_ of the proposed line, in a system of co-ordinates of a nature corresponding to that of the mode of generation considered. Thus, for example, the common definition of the _circle_ may evidently be regarded as being immediately the _polar equation_ of this curve, taking the centre of the circle for the pole. In the same way, the elementary definition of the _ellipse_ or of the _hyperbola_--as being the curve generated by a point which moves in such a manner that the sum or the difference of its distances from two fixed points remains constant--gives at once, for either the one or the other curve, the equation _y_ + _x_ = _c_, taking for the system of co-ordinates that in which the position of a point would be determined by its distances from two fixed points, and choosing for these poles the two given foci. In like manner, the common definition of any _cycloid_ would furnish directly, for that curve, the equation _y_ = _mx_; adopting as the co-ordinates of each point the arc which it marks upon a circle of invariable radius, measuring from the point of contact of that circle with a fixed line, and the rectilinear distance from that point of contact to a certain origin taken on that right line. We can make a.n.a.logous and equally easy verifications with respect to the customary definitions of spirals, of epicycloids, &c. We shall constantly find that there exists a certain system of co-ordinates, in which we immediately obtain a very simple equation of the proposed line, by merely writing algebraically the condition imposed by the mode of generation considered.
Besides its direct importance as a means of rendering perfectly apparent the necessary representation of every line by an equation, the preceding consideration seems to me to possess a true scientific utility, in characterizing with precision the princ.i.p.al general difficulty which occurs in the actual establishment of these equations, and in consequently furnis.h.i.+ng an interesting indication with respect to the course to be pursued in inquiries of this kind, which, by their nature, could not admit of complete and invariable rules. In fact, since any definition whatever of a line, at least among those which indicate a mode of generation, furnishes directly the equation of that line in a certain system of co-ordinates, or, rather, of itself const.i.tutes that equation, it follows that the difficulty which we often experience in discovering the equation of a curve, by means of certain of its characteristic properties, a difficulty which is sometimes very great, must proceed essentially only from the commonly imposed condition of expressing this curve a.n.a.lytically by the aid of a designated system of co-ordinates, instead of admitting indifferently all possible systems.
These different systems cannot be regarded in a.n.a.lytical geometry as being all equally suitable; for various reasons, the most important of which will be hereafter discussed, geometers think that curves should almost always be referred, as far as is possible, to _rectilinear co-ordinates_, properly so called. Now we see, from what precedes, that in many cases these particular co-ordinates will not be those with reference to which the equation of the curve will be found to be directly established by the proposed definition. The princ.i.p.al difficulty presented by the formation of the equation of a line really consists, then, in general, in a certain transformation of co-ordinates.
It is undoubtedly true that this consideration does not subject the establishment of these equations to a truly complete general method, the success of which is always certain; which, from the very nature of the subject, is evidently chimerical: but such a view may throw much useful light upon the course which it is proper to adopt, in order to arrive at the end proposed. Thus, after having in the first place formed the preparatory equation, which is spontaneously derived from the definition which we are considering, it will be necessary, in order to obtain the equation belonging to the system of co-ordinates which must be finally admitted, to endeavour to express in a function of these last co-ordinates those which naturally correspond to the given mode of generation. It is upon this last labour that it is evidently impossible to give invariable and precise precepts. We can only say that we shall have so many more resources in this matter as we shall know more of true a.n.a.lytical geometry, that is, as we shall know the algebraical expression of a greater number of different algebraical phenomena.
CHOICE OF CO-ORDINATES.