Kinship Organisations and Group Marriage in Australia - LightNovelsOnl.com
You're reading novel online at LightNovelsOnl.com. Please use the follow button to get notifications about your favorite novels and its latest chapters so you can come back anytime and won't miss anything.
[150] Sometimes but usually not, for Morgan is utterly inconsistent.
CHAPTER XII.
GROUP MARRIAGE AND THE TERMS OF RELATIONs.h.i.+P.
Mother and Child. Kurnai terms. Dieri evidence. _Noa._ Group Mothers.
Cla.s.sification and descriptive terms. Poverty of language. Terms express status. The savage view natural.
We may now turn to consider the terms of relations.h.i.+p from the point of view of marriage, more especially in connection with Australia. We have already seen that there are great difficulties in the way of Morgan's hypothesis that the names accurately represent the relations which formerly existed in the tribes which used them. I propose to discuss the matter here from a somewhat different standpoint.
It seems highly probable that if any individual term came into use, whether monogamy, patriarchal polygyny, "group marriage," or promiscuity prevailed, it would be that which expresses the relations.h.i.+p of a mother to her child. The only other possibility would be that in the first two conditions mentioned the relation of husband to wife might take precedence.
In actual practice we find that the name which a mother applies to her own child is applied by her equally to the children of the women whom her husband might have married. This state of things may obviously arise from one of three causes, (_a_) In the first place the name may have been originally that which a mother applied to her own son, and it may have been extended to those who were her nephews in a state of monogamy, or stepsons (=sons of other women by the same father) in a state of polygyny either with or without polyandry. (_b_) The theory that a name was applied originally to own and collateral relatives has already been discussed, so far as it refers to the "undivided commune." The case of regulated promiscuity is different and must be considered here. (_c_) On the other hand the name which she uses may have been expressive of tribal status or group status, and may have had nothing to do with descent.
It is unnecessary to say much about the first of these possibilities.
First, there is no evidence to show that such a thing has taken place; secondly, we can see no reason why such a thing should take place; thirdly, if such a change of meaning did take place, it is quite clear that we have no grounds for regarding the philological evidence for group marriage as having the slightest significance.
In connection with the second hypothesis--that the names actually represent the relations formerly existing, it may be well to preface the discussion by a few remarks on the regulation of marriage in Australia.
The rules by which the Australian native is bound, when he sets out to choose a wife, make the area of choice as a rule dependent on his status, that is to say, he must, in order to find a wife, go to another phratry, cla.s.s, totem-kin, or combination of two of these, members.h.i.+p of which depends on descent, direct or indirect; on the other hand he may be limited by regulations dependent on locality, that is to say he may have to take a wife from a group resident in a certain area. There is reason to suppose that the latter regulations are the outcome of earlier status regulations which have fallen into desuetude. However this may be, all that we are here concerned with is the fact that regulations in this case also are virtually dependent on descent, inasmuch as a man is not in practice free to reside where he likes, but remains in his own group, though occasionally he joins that of his wife (this does not apparently affect the exogamic rule). The groups are therefore to all intents and purposes totem-kins with male descent.
Taking the Kurnai as our example of the non-cla.s.s-organised groups, we find that the fraternal relations.h.i.+p once started goes on for ever; the result of this is that with few exceptions the whole of the intermarrying groups, so far as they are of the same generation, are brothers and sisters. Dr Howitt, whose authority on matters of Australian ethnology is final, recognises that on the principles on which group marriage is deduced from terms of relations.h.i.+p, this fact should point to the Kurnai being yet in the stage of the undivided commune (why, it is difficult to see, when they are definitely exogamous), but regards the argument from terms of relations.h.i.+p as untrustworthy in this instance. If it is not reliable in one case it may well be unreliable in all; we are ent.i.tled to ask supporters of the hypothesis of group marriage what differentiates this case from those in which they have no doubt of the validity of the philological argument.
Now if Dr Howitt's doubts as to the interpretation to be put upon the Kurnai terms of relations.h.i.+p are correct, we may reasonably, in the absence of proof that they originated in a different way from the Malayan terms, ask ourselves upon what basis the case for promiscuity rests. Beyond a few customs, and it will be shown below that it is unnecessary to regard them as survivals of a period when marriage was unknown, the proof is purely philological, and on examination the philological proof is found to be wanting.
Dr Howitt, in his recent book, rests the case for the undivided commune (i.e. promiscuity) on the Australian terms of relations.h.i.+p which he discusses, viz. those of the Dieri and the Kurnai. He will not admit that the Kurnai terms point to the undivided commune; we are therefore left with the Dieri terms. But the Dieri organisation, so far from being that of an undivided commune, is the two-phratry arrangement by which a man is by no means free to marry any woman in his tribe, but is limited to one-half of the women; further, tribal customs limit his choice still further and compel him to marry his mother's mother's brother's daughter's daughter (these terms do not refer to blood but so-called "tribal" relations.h.i.+p, i.e. it is a woman with a certain tribal status whom he has to marry). Where then does Dr Howitt find his proof of promiscuity?
We have, it is true, a certain number of tribal legends, according to which the phratry organisation was inst.i.tuted to prevent the marriage of too near kin. But, quite apart from the fact that tribal legends are not evidence, the legends merely point to a period when marriage was unregulated, when a man was free to marry any woman, not when he was _de facto_ or _de jure_ the husband of every woman. Even if it be proved beyond question that marriage was once unregulated, it does not follow that promiscuity prevailed.
The existence of the undivided commune is a proof of promiscuity only for those who discover proofs of group marriage in the divided commune, in other words in the terms of relations.h.i.+p and the customs of the ordinary two-phratry tribe of the present day. We may therefore let the decision of the question of the validity of terms of relations.h.i.+p as a proof of extensive connubial activities rest upon the discussion of the evidence to be drawn from the tribes selected by Dr Howitt and Messrs Spencer and Gillen, viz. the Dieri and the Urabunna.
It may however be pointed out that neither of these writers has dealt with the pa.s.sage from promiscuity to "group marriage," nor shown how under the former system terms of relations.h.i.+p could come into existence at all. With the difficulties we have dealt above.
We must now revert to the question of the origin of the so-called "terms of relations.h.i.+p." Are they expressive of kins.h.i.+p or only of status and duties? Neither Lewis Morgan nor the authorities on Australian marriage customs--Dr Howitt and Messrs Spencer and Gillen--discuss the question at length, but seem to regard it as an axiom (although they warn us that all European ideas of relations.h.i.+p must be dismissed when we deal with the cla.s.sificatory system) that all these terms may be interpreted on the hypothesis that the European relations.h.i.+ps to which they most nearly correspond actually existed in former times, not, as in Europe, between individuals, but between groups. The case on which Spencer and Gillen rely is that of the _unawa_ relations.h.i.+p. They argue that a man is _unawa_ to a whole group of women, one of whom is his individual wife; for this individual wife no special name exists, she is just _unawa_ (=_noa_) like all the other women he might have married. Consequently the marital relation must have existed formerly between the man in question and the whole group of _unawa_ women. The reasoning does not seem absolutely conclusive, and our doubts as to the validity of the argument are strengthened when we apply it to another case and find the results inconsistent with facts which are known to the lowest savage.
Not only has a man only one name for the women he might have married, and for the woman he actually did marry, but a mother has only one name for the son she actually bore, and for the sons of the women who, if they had become her husband's wives, would have borne him sons in her stead. From this fact by parity of reasoning we must draw the obvious conclusion that during the period when group marriage was the rule, individual mothers were unknown. If we are ent.i.tled to conclude from the fact that a man's wife bears the same name for him as all the other women whom he might have married, that he at one time was the husband of them all, then we are obviously equally ent.i.tled to conclude, from the fact that a woman's son is known to her by the same name as the sons of other women, either that during the period of group marriage she actually bore the sons of the other women or that the whole group of women produced their sons by their joint efforts. Finding that the term which is translated "son" is equally applied by the remainder of the group of women to the son of the individual woman, whose case we have been considering, we may discard the former hypothesis and come to the conclusion that if there was a period of group marriage there was also one of group motherhood. This interesting fact may be commended to the attention of zoologists.
It is perhaps unnecessary to pursue the argument any further. The single point on which Spencer and Gillen rely is sufficiently refuted by a single _reductio ad absurdum_. If more proof is needed it may be found in Dr Howitt's work[151]. We learn from him that a man is the younger brother of his maternal grandmother, and consequently the maternal grandfather of his second cousin. Surely it is not possible in this case to contend that the "terms of relations.h.i.+p" are expressive of anything but duties and status. It seems unreasonable to maintain in the interests of an hypothesis that a man can be his own great uncle and the son of more than one mother.
From the foregoing discussion it will be clear that there are very grave, if not insurmountable, difficulties in the way of regarding the "terms of relations.h.i.+p" as being in reality such. In reply to those who regard them as status terms it is urged that if they are not terms of relations.h.i.+p, then the savages have no terms of any sort to express relations.h.i.+ps which we regard as obvious, the implication being that this is unthinkable.
Now in the first place it may be pointed out that the converse is certainly true. Civilised man has a large number of terms of relations.h.i.+p, but he has none for such ideas as _noa_; a boy has no term for all men who might have been his father; a woman has no name for the children of all women who might have married her husband, if she had not antic.i.p.ated them. To the savage this is just as unthinkable as the converse seems to be to some civilised men.
In the second place it is perfectly obvious that the savage has, as a matter of fact, no names for the quite unmistakeable relations.h.i.+p of mother and child. The name which an Australian mother applies to her son, she applies equally to the sons of all other women of her own status; the name which a son applies to his mother, he applies equally to all the women of her status, whether married or unmarried, in old age, middle life, youth, or infancy. If there is no term for this relation we can hardly argue that the absence of terms for other relations is unthinkable.
Morgan attempted to meet this objection by urging that in a state of promiscuity a woman would apply the same name to the children of other women as to her own, because they were or might be by the same father.
But in the first place this a.s.sumes that the relations.h.i.+p to the father was considered rather than the relations.h.i.+p to the mother, and this is against all a.n.a.logy. In the second place, even granting Morgan's postulate, the relation of a mother to her son is not that of a wife to the children of other wives of a polygynous husband. Poverty of language is therefore established in this case, and may be taken for granted where the obvious relations.h.i.+ps are concerned.
It has been pointed out more than once that there are grave difficulties in the way of any hypothesis which a.s.sumes that terms of relations.h.i.+p, properly so called, were evolved in a state of pure promiscuity. It has now been shown that no intelligible account of the meaning of such terms can be given, even if we dismiss the difficulties just mentioned and a.s.sume that terms were somehow or other evolved, and a transition effected to a state of regulated promiscuity. If on the other hand we regard the "terms of relations.h.i.+p" as originally indicative of tribal status and suppose they have been transformed in the course of ages into "descriptive" terms such as we use in everyday life, the difficulties vanish.
For one proof of this hypothesis we need look no further than the terms of relations.h.i.+p applied by a mother to her own (and other) children, an ill.u.s.tration which has already done duty more than once. It is abundantly clear that what this term expresses is not relations.h.i.+p but status, the relation of one generation to the next in the Malayan system, of the half of a generation to the next generation in the same moiety of the tribe among the Dieri, and so on.
It is admitted even by believers in group marriage that the terms of relations.h.i.+p do not correspond to anything actually existing; beyond the "survivals" which we shall consider below, they can produce no shadow of proof that the terms ever did correspond to actual relations.h.i.+ps, as they understand them. They can give no proof whatever that they did not express status.
It is therefore a fair hypothesis that _unawa_ (_noa_) and similar terms express status and not relations.h.i.+p. From the example of mother and son we see that the Australian does not select for distinction by a special term that bond which is most obvious both to him and us. It is therefore by no means surprising that by _unawa_ he should mean, not the existence of marital relations, but their possibility, from a 'legal' point of view. Just as he is struck, not by the genetic relation between mother and son, but by the fact that they belong to different generations, so in the case of husband and wife the _existence_ of marital relations between them is neglected, and the point selected for emphasis is the _legality_ of such marital relations, whether existent or not.
It is singular that anyone should regard this savage view of life as anything but natural. For the Australian the due observance of the marriage regulations is a tribal matter; their breach, whether the connection be by marriage or free love, is a matter of more than private concern. The relations of a man with his legal wife however concern other members of the tribe but little. Public opinion among the Dieri, it is true, condemns the unfaithful wife, but her punishment is left to the husband; among the Kamilaroi the tribe indeed takes the matter up but only on the complaint of the husband; and generally speaking it is the husband who, possibly with his totemic brethren, pursues the abductor. We have therefore in this insistence on the legal status of the couple and the comparative indifference to the husband's rights a sufficiently exact parallel to the insistence on status and not marital relations in the use of the term _unawa_.
The course of evolution has been, not, as group-marriagers contend, from group to individual terms of relations.h.i.+p but from terms descriptive of status to terms descriptive of relations.h.i.+p.
It is, in fact, on any hypothesis, impossible to deny this. Whatever terms of relations.h.i.+p may have meant in the past, no believer in group marriage contends that they represent anything actually existing. But this is equivalent to admitting that they express status and not relations.h.i.+p, and no proof has ever been given that they were ever anything else.
FOOTNOTES:
[151] p. 163.
CHAPTER XIII.
PIRRAURU.
Theories of group marriage. Meaning of group. Dieri customs. Tippa-malku marriage. Obscure points. _Pirrauru._ Obscure points. Relation of _pirrauru_ to _tippa-malku_ unions. Kurnandaburi. Wakelbura customs.
Kurnai organisation. Position of widow. _Piraungaru_ of Urabunna.
_Pirrauru_ and group marriage. _Pirrauru_ not a survival. Result of scarcity of women. Duties of _Pirrauru_ spouses. _Piraungaru_: obscure points.
We now come to the marriage customs of the Australian natives of the present day and the supposed survivals of group marriage. In dealing with the question of group marriage we are met with a preliminary difficulty. No one has formulated a definition of this state, and the interpretations of the term are very diverse.
Fison, for example, says[152] group marriage does not necessarily imply actual giving in marriage or cohabitation; all it means is a marital right or rather qualification which comes by birth. He argues however on a later page[153] that Nair polyandry, which is more properly termed promiscuity, is group marriage. Much the same view is taken by A.H.
Post[154], who regards the theory of pure promiscuity and the undivided commune as untenable.
Kohler, on the other hand[155], speaks of group marriage as existing among the Omahas, a patrilineal tribe, be it remarked; but means by that no more than adelphic polygyny.
Spencer and Gillen criticise Westermarck's use of the term "pretended group marriage" and a.s.sert it to be a fact among the Urabunna. On the very next page group marriage is spoken of as having preceded the present state of things. Both statements cannot be true.
For the purposes of the present work I understand group marriage to mean promiscuity limited by regulations based on organisations such as age-grades, phratries, totem-kins, or local groups.
The fact is that Spencer and Gillen and other writers on Australia use the term group merely as a noun of mult.i.tude. They do not mean by group, in one sense, anything more than a number of persons. In this sense they speak of group marriage (=polygamy) at the present day--a fact which is not peculiar to Australia and which no one is concerned to deny. By a quite illegitimate transformation of meaning they also apply the term group to a portion of a tribe distinguished by a cla.s.s name and (or or) term of relations.h.i.+p and mean by group marriage cla.s.s promiscuity. They do not even perceive that they make this transition, for otherwise Messrs Spencer and Gillen could hardly a.s.sail Dr Westermarck for using the term "pretended group marriage" which is quite accurate as a description of group (=cla.s.s) marriage or promiscuity. Even if there were justification for a.s.suming that group marriage (=polygamy) is a lineal descendant of group marriage (=cla.s.s promiscuity), nothing would be gained by using the term group marriage of both. In the subsequent discussion it will be made clear that whatever their causal connection, there is hardly a single point of similarity between them beyond the fact that the s.e.xual relations are in neither case monogamous. It is therefore to be hoped that the supporters of the hypothesis of group marriage will in the future encourage clear thinking by not using the same term for different forms of s.e.xual union.
I now proceed to discuss the alleged survival of group marriage and other Australian marriage customs.
Taking the Dieri tribe as our example the following state of things is found to prevail. The tribe is divided into exogamous moieties, Matteri and Kararu; subject to restrictions dependent on kins.h.i.+p, with which we are not immediately concerned, any Matteri may marry any Kararu. A reciprocal term, _noa_[156], is in use to denote the status of those who may marry each other. This _noa_ relations.h.i.+p is sometimes cited as a proof of the existence of group marriage. As a matter of fact it is no more evidence of group marriage than the fact that a man is _noa_ to all the unmarried women of England except a few, is proof of the existence of group marriage in England; or the fact that _femme_ in French means both wife and woman is an argument for the existence of promiscuity in France in Roman or post-Roman times.
A ceremony, usually performed in infancy or childhood, changes the relations.h.i.+p of a _noa_ male and female from _noa-mara_ to _tippa-malku_. The step is taken by the mothers with the concurrence of the girl's maternal uncles, and is in fact betrothal. Apparently no further ceremony is necessary to const.i.tute a marriage. At any rate nothing is said as to that.